Sociologica. V.18 N.1 (2024), 25–63
ISSN 1971-8853

The Interpretation of Cultures: Geertz Is Still in Town

Simon SusenSchool of Policy and Global Affairs, City, University of London (United Kingdom) https://www.city.ac.uk/about/people/academics/simon-susen
ORCID https://orcid.org/0000-0003-0643-1891

Simon Susen is Professor of Sociology at City, University of London (United Kingdom). He received his PhD from the University of Cambridge (United Kingdom) in 2007. He is Affiliate Professor of Sociology at the Universidad Andrés Bello in Santiago (Chile). In addition, he is Associate Member of the Bauman Institute (United Kingdom) and, together with Bryan S. Turner, Editor of the Journal of Classical Sociology.

Submitted: 2023-12-14 – Revised version: 2024-03-31 – Accepted: 2024-05-05 – Published: 2024-06-20

Abstract

Clifford Geertz’s The Interpretation of Cultures (1973) is widely regarded as one of the most important contributions to the humanities and social sciences in general and anthropology in particular. On its 50th anniversary, the literature drawing on this monumental work is so vast that it is hard to see how anything of significance may still be added to the wide range of insights gained from the in-depth engagement with its main argument. The noticeable differences in opinion between followers and detractors of Geertz’s project notwithstanding, most commentators will agree that The Interpretation of Cultures, having dominated the agenda of Anglophone anthropology for at least two decades after its publication, has had a major and lasting impact on neighbouring disciplines and subdisciplines—notably sociology, social psychology, politics, history, philosophy, and cultural studies. This paper aims to demonstrate that the key conceptual components of Geertz’s enterprise can be located in his case for an interpretive theory of culture, epitomized in the methodological commitment to providing a ‘thick description’. The first half of this paper comprises an inquiry into the core assumptions underlying Geertz’s defence of this endeavour, before moving, in the second half, to an assessment of some controversial issues arising from his approach.

Keywords: Anthropology; culture; Geertz (Clifford); interpretation; thick description.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to two anonymous reviewers for their valuable and constructive comments on an earlier version of this article. Furthermore, I would like to thank the Guest Editors, Matteo Bortolini and Andrea Cossu, for encouraging me to incorporate most of the changes requested by the reviewers. All errors remain my own.

Clifford Geertz’s The Interpretation of Cultures (1973)1 is widely regarded as one of the most important contributions to the humanities and social sciences in general and anthropology in particular. On its 50th anniversary, the literature drawing on this monumental work is so vast that it is hard to see how anything of significance may still be added to the wide range of insights gained from the in-depth engagement with its main argument. The noticeable differences in opinion between followers and detractors of Geertz’s project notwithstanding, most commentators will agree that The Interpretation of Cultures, having dominated the agenda of Anglophone anthropology for at least two decades after its publication, has had a major and lasting impact on neighbouring disciplines and subdisciplines—notably sociology, social psychology, politics, history, philosophy, and cultural studies.

The following analysis aims to demonstrate that the key conceptual components of Geertz’s enterprise can be located in his case for an interpretive theory of culture, epitomized in the methodological commitment to providing a ‘thick description’2. The first half of this paper comprises an inquiry into the core assumptions underlying Geertz’s defence of this endeavour, before moving, in the second half, to a discussion of some controversial issues arising from his approach.

In relation to the first task, the paper seeks to illustrate that Geertz’s account of culture requires a systematic assessment of various crucial relationships: (1) culture and ‘thick description’, (2) culture and ethnography, (3) culture and anthropology, (4) culture and meaning, (5) culture and (un)familiarity, (6) culture and science, (7) culture and semiotics, (8) culture and coherence, (9) culture and context, and (10) culture and interpretation. The thorough examination of these dimensions indicates that Geertz’s account of culture is far more nuanced than a catch-all summary may suggest.

In relation to the second task, the paper seeks to shed light on contentious matters arising from Geertz’s perspective, positing that valuable lessons can be learnt from exploring the extent to which a range of analytical oppositions may be better understood as conceptual pairs, which are vital ingredients of critical social inquiry and which, as interdependent and complementary components, contribute to overcoming counterproductive divisions in the humanities and social sciences: (1) interpretation and explanation, (2) the micro and the macro, (3) the particular and the universal, (4) reality and representation, (5) nature and culture, (6) interpretations of culture and cultures of interpretation, (7) cognitive orders and normative orders, (8) the public and the private, (9) common humanity and cultural diversity, (10) ordinary knowledge and scientific knowledge, (11) correlation and causation, (12) familiarity and strangeness, (13) ontology and epistemology, (14) functionalism and interpretivism, and (15) Feldanschauung and Weltanschauung.

The paper concludes by arguing that, having considered both the contributions and the limitations of Geertz’s framework, it becomes possible not only to appreciate the theoretical and practical challenges involved in the interpretation of cultures but also to grasp the significance of the conceptual pairs that are essential for pursuing fruitful and imaginative forms of critical social research.

1 Geertz’s Project

1.1 Culture and ‘thick description’

According to Geertz, an interpretive theory of culture entails a methodological commitment to providing a ‘thick description’3, a term introduced by the British philosopher Gilbert Ryle4. An intellectual undertaking of this kind represents ‘an elaborate venture’5, which obliges us to draw a distinction between two principal types of description: on the one hand, ‘thin description’, which is founded on surface-level observations of human behaviour; on the other hand, ‘thick description’, which contextualizes human behaviour and, thus, endeavours to comprehend it by taking into consideration the environment in which it takes place.

Ethnographic work, understood in the classical sense, involves a series of noteworthy activities—such as establishing a rapport between researcher(s) and participant(s), selecting a pool of informants, transcribing texts, developing genealogies, mapping fields, keeping a diary, and so forth. Ultimately, these methodological tools are employed with the purpose of studying and comprehending a group of actors in their social setting, permitting the ethnographic researcher to produce a (theoretically informed and empirically based) narrative account of cultural practices, structures, and arrangements.

Geertz’s reflections on the differences between a twitch and a wink is a case in point6. Through the lens of a ‘thin description’, the act of contracting one’s eyelids may be perceived in merely physiological terms and, hence, as a twitch. Through the lens of a ‘thick description’, the same phenomenon may be interpreted as a (psychologically motivated, historically situated, socially contingent, and culturally codified) process whereby a person seeks to communicate something to someone else through a wink. If the latter, rather than the former, is the case, then the act of contracting one’s eyelids can be regarded as an act of winking, in the sense that something is being communicated (a) intentionally, (b) to another actor or group of actors, (c) with the goal of conveying a message in a secretive manner, and (d) to accomplish this without cognizance of the rest of the company.

Far from aiming to lay bare what anyone actually intends or means, however, Geertz is interested in explicating the larger system of meanings—that is, the semiotic system—through which people can participate in communicative processes (including winking). In other words, his primary concern is not to establish whether, in a given context, actors are trying to convey something in an enigmatic manner, to reveal what their fundamental motives are, and/or to enlighten us about what they are hoping to accomplish by performing a concealed or encrypted communicative act (such as winking). Rather, he is interested in contextualizing and understanding the semiotic code within and through which a culturally competent person can engage in communicative acts.

When attempting to provide a ‘thick description’, one is immersed in the realm of ethnography: its object of study is ‘a stratified hierarchy of meaningful structures’7, practices, and arrangements. This symbolically mediated pecking order sets the parameters for the production, perception, appreciation, and interpretation of actions, or sets of actions, implying that, in principle, anything can be interpreted ‘as a cultural category8.

Ethnographic descriptions are ‘extraordinarily thick’9 in that data are never simply ‘data’. Rather, they are the researcher’s ‘own constructions of other people’s constructions of what they and their compatriots are up to’10. Just as ordinary actors navigate their everyday lives by virtue of numerous material and symbolic constructions, so do those who seek to study and to comprehend them. Constructions of other people’s constructions are both constructive and reconstructive. They are constructive insofar as researchers have to mobilize their cognitive resources, projecting their own (perspective-, meaning-, and value-laden) concepts and beliefs upon those whose lives they scrutinize. At the same time, they are reconstructive insofar as they are supposed to capture their object of inquiry as accurately as possible, situating it in the contexts in which it is embedded and, by implication, in the relationally constituted spaces it inhabits.

To do justice to the complexity of this task, however, it is essential that the ethnographer recognize the challenges arising from identifying the factors that lurk in the background and, therefore, escape our common-sense grasp of the world: ‘most of what we need to comprehend a particular event, ritual, custom, idea, or whatever is insinuated as background information before the thing itself is directly examined’11. To put it bluntly, ethnographic research is as much about observing what seems obvious to the observer as about uncovering what can be found beneath the surface. To be sure, this twofold objective is not predicated on the assumption that crucial information is deliberately or unwittingly hidden by the research participants. Rather, it is based on the insight that, due to its multidimensional constitution and multifactorial determinacy, every social situation is far more complex than it appears to be at first glance.

1.2 Culture and ethnography

According to Geertz, it is erroneous to endorse ‘a view of anthropological research as rather more of an observational and rather less of an interpretive activity than it really is’12. Granted, every social science—including anthropology—has a ‘factual base’13, which constitutes ‘the hard rock, insofar as there is any, of the whole enterprise’14. This solid ground, however, is the empirical foundation of symbolically mediated and culturally codified practices, structures, and arrangements.

To accept that ‘ethnography is thick description’15 requires recognizing that ‘[d]oing ethnography is like trying to read (in the sense of “construct a reading of”) a manuscript-foreign, faded, full of ellipses, incoherencies, suspicious emendations, and tendentious commentaries’16. Reading—understood in these terms—is not only a technical matter of decoding, deciphering, or decrypting but also an interpretive exercise in looking at the world from the perspective shared and co-constructed by ordinary actors. This co-agential outlook manifests itself in different ways: collective representations, collective consciousness17, and collective imagination (at the ideological level); practices, habits, and conventions (at the behavioural level); social structures, arrangements, and organizations (at the institutional level).

Doing ethnography requires the ability to ‘construct a reading of’18 texts written not in ‘conventionalized graphs of sound’19 but, rather, in ‘transient examples of shaped behaviour’20—and, by extension, of varying degrees of social institutionalization. Given their interest in and engagement with the (often messy and constantly evolving) constitution of social life, ethnographers cannot rely on standardized, routinized, and automatized forms of data collection. Committed to the participatory study of behavioural, ideological, and institutional modes of sociality, which are ‘superimposed upon or knotted into one another’21, ethnographers are confronted with several interrelated challenges: (a) the methodological challenge of examining, (b) the theoretical challenge of explaining, (c) the terminological challenge of offering a vocabulary for, (d) the epistemological challenge of identifying different types of knowledge emerging within, and (e) the empirical challenge of absorbing the presence of individual and collective forces, which—as structural and agential variables that are ‘at once strange, irregular, and inexplicit’22—govern everyday life.

Caught between the scientific tasks of objectification, observation, and explanation, on the one hand, and the hermeneutic tasks of immersion, interpretation, and understanding, on the other, ethnographic descriptions—in the Geertzian sense—contain four characteristics: (a) they are interpretive, (b) they are interpretive of the flow of social discourse, (c) their processes of interpretation are aimed at rescuing ‘the “said” of such discourse from its perishing occasions and fix it in perusable terms’23, and (d) they are microscopic.

This is not to suggest that ‘there are no large-scale anthropological interpretations of whole societies, civilizations, world events, and so on’24. Indeed, ethnographic descriptions would be shortsighted if they failed to consider the macro-historical settings in which micro-historical events are situated and the macro-sociological factors by which micro-sociological dynamics are shaped. Moreover, there is an array of anthropological constants, which—owing to their ineluctable presence in forms of life—ethnographic descriptions cannot ignore. The tension between cross-cultural universals and cross-cultural variations is as central to anthropology as to any other social-scientific discipline concerned with the constitutive features by which humanity is either united or divided. The question is not whether any ‘all-too-human constancies25 exist. Rather, the question is whether these are outweighed by all-too-human differences.

Doing ethnography does not mean that those involved in the research should aim ‘either to become natives (a compromised word in any case) or to mimic them’26. On the contrary, it is imperative that ethnographers be capable of maintaining a healthy scientific distance from their object(s) of study. Insofar as they succeed in doing so, they can combine the third-person perspective of the observer(s) with the first-person perspective of the participant(s), instead of claiming that one is epistemically superior to the other.

As Geertz—drawing on Stanley Cavell27—points out, if ‘speaking for someone else seems to be a mysterious process’28, the main reason for this is that ‘speaking to someone does not seem mysterious enough’29. Both in everyday life and in everyday research, the third-person perspectives of observers and the first-person perspectives of participants are deeply intertwined:

  • As lifeworld-inhabitants, we are both participants (contributing to the material and symbolic construction of reality) and observers (grappling with and making judgements about the constitution of reality).

  • As critical analysts, we are both participants (contributing to the production, reception, and circulation of both scientific and non-scientific reflections) and observers (mobilizing terminological, epistemological, theoretical, methodological, and empirical tools for the study of reality).

By comprehending the nature and purpose of ethnography, as well as the orientations and practices of ethnographers, we can grasp ‘what anthropological analysis amounts to as a form of knowledge’30. In short, doing ethnography reveals a great deal about the project of interpretive anthropology.

1.3 Culture and anthropology

The concept of culture lies at the core of anthropology’s disciplinary identity. It is not self-evident, however, how the concept should be defined from an anthropological perspective. Warning his readers of an inflationary use of anthropology’s most central concept, Geertz makes a case for a clearly defined understanding of culture. On this account, a narrow and specialized conception of culture is both theoretically and empirically more insightful than a broad and elastic one, which is epitomized in E.B. Tylor’s well-known ‘most complex whole’ formulation31. It is not uncommon for such forms of ‘cultural holism’—according to which everything is cultural, just as culture is everything—to be implicitly or explicitly invoked in general introductions to anthropology.

A good example of this trend is Clyde Kluckhohn’s Mirror for Man32, in which—as pointed out by Geertz—the concept of culture is defined in a dozen ways33: (a) civilizational34; (b) sociological35; (c) mental, emotional, and ideological36; (d) symbolic37; (e) behavioural38; (f) educational and transgenerational39; (g) habitual and consequential40; (h) educational and behavioural41; (i) normative and regulative42; (j) technical, instrumental, and social43; (k) historical and motivational44; (l) orientational, representational, and environmental45.

While expressing a degree of sympathy with Kluckhohn’s attempt at developing a differentiated account of culture, Geertz warns that an overly eclectic, if not catch-all, approach runs the risk of failing to recognize that ‘it is necessary to choose’46 and, thus, to provide a workable definition of this central concept. The concept of culture endorsed by Geertz, then, is ‘essentially a semiotic one’47. Similar to Max Weber’s Verstehende Soziologie, Geertz’s interpretive anthropology is predicated on the assumption that ‘man is an animal suspended in webs of significance he himself has spun’48. Culture can be regarded as the totality of those webs, which are not only socially constructed but also symbolically mediated by, and materially embedded in, local and global networks of human actions and interactions. On this view, anthropology is ‘not an experimental science in search of law but an interpretive one in search of meaning49. In brief, interpretive anthropology is a form of cultural analysis, rather than a type of experimental science, let alone scientism.

While advocating an interpretive conception of anthropology, Geertz rejects mentalist, idealist, and occultist approaches to culture—that is, explanatory frameworks that tend to reduce culture to a merely cognitive, conceptual, and/or hidden affair. In a more general sense, he is wary of the dichotomous thinking by which much of anthropology has been marked ever since it came into existence. This mode of reasoning is illustrated in counterproductive divisions, such as subjectivism vs. objectivism, idealism vs. materialism, mentalism vs. behaviourism, impressionism vs. positivism—to mention only a few. These (and other) paradigmatic dualisms manifest themselves in varying degrees of academic tribalism and increasingly polarized ways of defining and defending discipline-specific (particularly terminological, epistemological, theoretical, methodological, and empirical) tools. Ultimately, this trend results in the proliferation of fruitless intellectual divisions, preventing social scientists from combining insights gained from competing traditions of thought.

Different social-scientific approaches offer different perspectives on the ‘ontological status’50 of culture (and, by extension, on the terminological, epistemological, theoretical, methodological, and empirical tools by which it should be studied). Irrespective of one’s interpretation, it would be erroneous to present culture as ‘a self-contained “superorganic” reality with forces and purposes of its own’51, since such a totalizing move would oblige us ‘to reify it’52. To put it bluntly, a culturalist conception of the social is no less reductive than its economistic counterpart. And yet, the idea that culture is located ‘in the minds and hearts of men’53—which is central to cognitivist and mentalist approaches to forms of life—is equally problematic. In fact, this notion is common among proponents of ethnoscience, componential analysis, and—crucially—cognitive anthropology54. For Geertz, this cognitivist fallacy indicates that ‘extreme subjectivism is married to extreme formalism’55.

Whether we are dealing with the cognitivist reduction of culture to a merely mental or psychological affair, the subjectivist reduction of culture to a phenomenon located in and defined by individuals, the formalist reduction of culture to an object of study graspable only by mathematics and logic, the behaviourist reduction of culture to a sequence of actions and interactions determined by environmental conditioning, or the idealist reduction of culture to spatiotemporally contingent sets of concepts and representations—none of these outlooks can do justice to the complexity of culture, notably in terms of its constitution, functioning, and development (both within and across different contexts).

1.4 Culture and meaning

Far from being reducible to ‘the conceptual manipulation of discovered facts, a logical reconstruction of a mere reality’56, whose inner workings are determined by ‘autogenous principles of order’57, anthropological inquiry is a mode of cultural analysis58 that involves ‘guessing at meanings, assessing the guesses, and drawing explanatory conclusions from the better guesses’59. It could not be further removed from the transcendental belief in the possibility of ‘discovering the Continent of Meaning and mapping out its bodiless landscape’60, as if cultural analysis were motivated by the enlightening mission of seeking to uncover the underlying mechanisms that govern the material and symbolic construction of reality.

In the spirit of the later Wittgenstein, Geertz insists that ‘[c]ulture is public because meaning is’61. Just as, according to the later Wittgenstein, ‘[t]he meaning of a word is its use in the language’62, the value of a culture is its use in a particular context. There is no such thing as an entirely private language and no such thing as an entirely private culture. Language and culture are products of the symbolically mediated and materially anchored actions and interactions taking place between human subjects.

Since the earlier Husserl63 and the later Wittgenstein64, the widespread rejection of ‘privacy theories of meaning’65 has been an integral part of the humanities and social sciences—from philosophy and linguistics to sociology and anthropology. As a general trend, it reflects the widely shared conviction that ‘culture consists of socially established structures of meaning66, mobilized by human actors navigating the objective, normative, and subjective realms of their existence. Culture has a strong cognitive dimension, in that it permeates a person’s dispositional apparatus of perception, appreciation, and interpretation. At the same time, culture has a pronounced relational dimension, in that it shapes a person’s way of encountering, engaging with, and working upon the world. Culture is a manifestation, vehicle, and engine of intersubjectivity.

1.5 Culture and (un)familiarity

One of the most striking features of cultural (including inter- and cross-cultural) dynamics is the relationship between familiarity and unfamiliarity—or, to be precise, between degrees of familiarity and degrees of unfamiliarity67. As pointed out by the later Wittgenstein68, given the (in many cases, profound) differences between forms of life, a person from one culture may perceive a person from another culture as ‘a complete enigma’69 (and vice versa). When we fail to understand each other due to cultural differences, ‘[w]e cannot find our feet with them’70. When this happens, we experience the full force of cultural (and often linguistic) incommensurability, which makes us realize the tangible consequences of interpretive inaccessibility. Put in Kantian terms, such an experience makes the foreign or unfamiliar culture appear like a noumenal realm (that is, ‘culture in itself’), to which we do not have access and whose constitution is only inferable through our superficial decoding of a phenomenal realm (that is, ‘culture as it appears to us’)71.

Geertz draws attention to a curious paradox: on the one hand, we are confronted with ‘[t]he great natural variation of cultural forms’72 across the world, indicating the high degree of contingency permeating the spatiotemporally conditions that undergird the existence of humanity; on the other hand, we are faced with ‘the biological unity of the human species’73, which transcends socially constructed boundaries and provides us with a sense of universality, based on a set of anthropological constants, which distinguish us from other sentient beings, irrespective of their role in the construction of reality.

As members of a species whose members are divided by several sociological variables, one of which is culture, most—if not all—of us are familiar not only with the feeling of familiarity but also with the feeling of unfamiliarity: we may be in sync with a cultural environment, especially when we experience it as broadly aligned with our personal identity; we may be out of sync with a cultural environment, especially when we experience it as largely misaligned with our personal identity. Human life is a constant back-and-forth between experiences of familiarity and experiences of unfamiliarity.

1.6 Culture and science

The quest for evidence-based and logically defensible truth claims is central to modernity’s attempt to make the world more and more controllable74 by virtue of a ‘new positive science75. Narrowly defined versions of this project, however, tend to result in dogmatically pursued variants of scientism, which ignore, or deny, the extent to which human reality is socially constructed76—including the extent to which its constitution, functioning, and development77 are contingent upon symbolically mediated actions and interactions performed by meaning-seeking beings.

In anthropological terms, symbolism is the ‘new key’ to understanding how the human mind has transformed the primal need to express oneself78. Understanding the nature of understanding—and, on a metatheoretical level, understanding the understanding of the nature of understanding—can be regarded as a major challenge for the humanities and social sciences, from hermeneutics and phenomenology to social psychology, micro-sociology, interpretive sociology, and interpretive anthropology. These interpretive—if not, interpretivist—endeavours emphasize not only the perspective-, meaning-, and value-laden constitution of social reality but also the degree to which monolithic and monoparadigmatic approaches fail to account for the multilayered composition of the objective, normative, and subjective realms that humans inhabit.

And yet, even if reductive frameworks (whether these be cognitivist, subjectivist, formalist, behaviourist, idealist, or otherwise) do ‘not explain everything, not even everything human’79, they still explain something, albeit in a highly limited and questionable fashion. Two key questions that arise in this context are (a) how to distinguish between non-reductive and reductive approaches and (b) how to distinguish between scientific and non-scientific (including pseudo-scientific) approaches. The ‘demarcation problem’80, therefore, poses numerous challenges, notably in relation to (a) the question of where to draw the line between defensible and indefensible explanatory reductions and (b) the question of where to draw the line between what counts as science and what does not count as science.

Albert Einstein’s famous dictum that ‘[e]verything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler’81, captures the complexity of this task. Non-reductive and scientific endeavours should make everything (including extremely complicated issues) as simple as possible. Their reductive and non-scientific (comprising pseudo-scientific) counterparts, however, make them simpler than they actually are.

It is no accident that, with the exception of Skinnerian versions of behaviourism and intelligence testing, operationalism ‘as a methodological dogma’82 has become increasingly marginalized in the contemporary social sciences. For all its limitations and shortcomings, including its tendency to reduce potentially complex social phenomena to mere ‘operations’83, these approaches have one advantage: they oblige us to acknowledge that, in order ‘to understand what a science is84 and, by implication, how it really functions, one needs to ‘look in the first instance not at its theories or its findings, and certainly not at what its apologists say about it’85. Rather, one ‘should look at what the practitioners of it do86. In other words, a powerful advantage of operationalist approaches is that—owing to their pragmatist spirit—they require us to challenge and to go beyond what scientists preach. To this end, it is essential to examine what they do when pursuing research, including the strategies they employ when positioning themselves in relation to their collaborators and competitors as well as, more generally, in relation to other actors in their respective fields.

1.7 Culture and semiotics

The principal aim of anthropology may be defined as ‘the enlargement of the universe of human discourse’87. While this is not anthropology’s sole objective (and while, in one form or another, it is pursued by various other disciplines), it provides a strong justification for ‘a semiotic concept of culture88—that is, for an approach committed to the study of signs and symbols and of their meaning and use. From a semiotic point of view, culture is not reducible to an anonymous power or force, working—paradoxically, both ‘through our bodies’ and ‘behind our backs’—in a causalist fashion and determining every inch of our being. It is not the case that culture is so omnipresent and omnipotent that it is capable of hijacking the physical, social, and personal dimensions of our existence, in such a way that these are not only permeated but also determined by its normative codes and modes of functioning. While human actions and interactions are unavoidably power-laden, they are not always power-driven89. While human actions and interactions are unavoidably culture-laden, they are not always culture-driven. Put differently, all social practices are power- and culture-permeated, but not all of them are power- and culture-motivated.

Rather than ascribing causal power to culture, an interpretive anthropology conceives of it in semiotic—and, by implication, contextual—terms. On this account, culture is a context within which social phenomena (whether these belong to the micro-, meso-, or macro-spheres of human existence) can ‘be intelligibly—that is, thickly—described’90. Obviously, the question of whether such a (cultural) context is familiar or unfamiliar to those experiencing and/or studying it is crucial. The old cliché that anthropology is all about making the familiar strange and the strange familiar persists to this day. This laudable mission, however, is transferable to other academic disciplines. Scientific endeavours that succeed in shedding light on the underlying forces that escape our common-sense perception of reality make the unfamiliar familiar. Scientific endeavours that succeed in challenging and breaking free from everyday preconceptions of reality make the familiar unfamiliar. Both missions—that is, both one’s familiarization with the unfamiliar and one’s defamiliarization of the familiar—are essential to the pursuit of a critical social science.

Addressing this task, interpretive anthropology advocates an action-oriented approach, commonly associated with a strong emphasis on the paradigm of Verstehen91. The interpretive approach proposed by Geertz, however, differs from classical Verstehen-focused methods (à la Dilthey and Weber)92 in that it is concerned with understanding semiotic codes, rather than with performing an empathetic interpretation of people’s largely unconscious assumptions, intentions, and motives93.

In anthropology (as in any other social science), it is important to draw a distinction between one’s object of study and one’s mode of study. The former is ontological in the sense that it refers to a type of being situated in the world. The latter is methodological in the sense that it refers to the means by which a particular component of the world is examined. Whether they do so as insiders or outsiders, ethnographers seek to gain an understanding of social realms by immersing themselves in them. Their ‘anthropological writings are themselves interpretations’94 of their object(s) of inquiry. To be clear, ordinary actors (or ‘natives’) are as interpretive as academic researchers. Yet, whereas the former rely largely on first-order interpretations, the latter generate second-order (or even third-order) interpretations. First-order interpretations permit natives to inhabit ‘their’ culture through the taken-for-granted assumptions of their worldview. Second-order (or even third-order) interpretations, by contrast, enable researchers to convert other cultures into objects of scientific investigation.

For Geertz, the sociological differences between ‘natives’ and ‘researchers’ manifest themselves not only in the epistemological differences between ‘first-order interpretations’ and ‘second-order/third-order interpretations’, the methodological differences between ‘insider involvement’ and ‘outsider observation’, and the ontological differences between ‘cultural being’ and ‘cultural analysis’ but also in the functional differences between ‘substance’ and ‘representation’. Culture is ubiquitous. It exists everywhere, in the sense that it permeates every aspect (including seemingly non-cultural aspects) of human life. By contrast, ‘anthropology exists in the book, the article, the lecture, the museum display, or, sometimes nowadays, the film’95. It is present in particular meta-cultural realms—that is, in realms whose main function consists in reflecting upon culture as both a vehicle of human co-existence and a vehicle of a symbolically mediated transcendence of material immanence.

To become aware of culture—as both a problematizable object of study and a constitutive part of human existence—is ‘to realize that the line between mode of representation and substantive content is as undrawable in cultural analysis as it is in painting’96. If anything, the line between its mode of representation and its substantive content is blurred and constantly being renegotiated, not least because the latter is part of the former, just as the former is part of the latter. Put differently, there are no cultural depictions without cultural existence, just as there is no cultural existence without cultural depictions.

The blurring of the line between mode of representation and substantive content ‘seems to threaten the objective status of anthropological knowledge by suggesting that its source is not social reality but scholarly artifice’97. At the same time, it seems to undermine the ontological status of anthropological existence by promoting the inflationary notion that culture is everywhere and nowhere. If ‘ethnography is thick description and ethnographers [are] those who are doing the describing’98, then the key question that arises is whether—in Geertz’s phraseology—‘it sorts winks from twitches and real winks from mimicked ones’99 and, thus, whether it succeeds in distinguishing between (merely) physiological and (essentially) motivational acts.

1.8 Culture and coherence

The relationship between culture and coherence is far from straightforward. On the one hand, ‘coherence cannot be the major test of validity for a cultural description’100, since social life is fragile, messy, and unpredictable. On the other hand, ‘[c]ultural systems must have a minimal degree of coherence’101, since social life is not viable unless it is relatively stable, organized, and predictable. Cultural systems, however, would implode without the modes of behaviour by which they are produced, reproduced, and potentially transformed. Indeed, the concept of behaviour needs to be taken seriously by anthropologists, ‘because it is through the flow of behaviour—or, more precisely, social action—that cultural forms find articulation’102. All symbolically mediated actions and interactions—embedded in language, consciousness, culture, artefacts, and so forth—‘draw their meaning from the role they play (Wittgenstein would say their “use”) in an ongoing pattern of life, not from any intrinsic relationships they bear to one another’103. Words derive their meanings from the way they are used104. Language games obtain their existential significance from the fact that they are—at once—manifestations, vehicles, and engines of forms of life.

Viewed in this (socio-holistic) light, a ‘hermetic’ or ‘isolationist’ conception of culture is untenable. If culture is regarded ‘as a symbolic system (the catch phrase is, “in its own terms”), by isolating its elements, specifying the internal relationships among those elements, and then characterizing the whole system in some general way’105, the extent to which it permeates all aspects of social life, while itself being permeated by them, is overlooked. Such a narrow approach runs the risk of ‘locking cultural analysis away from its proper object, the informal logic of actual life’106, which is irreducible to the self-referential logic of reductive frameworks. Whether these be defended as versions of cognitivism, subjectivism, formalism, behaviourism, or idealism (or, in discipline-parasitic terms, as psychologism, sociologism, or anthropologism), they fall into the trap of schematicism107.

For Geertz, there is no doubt that ‘[n]othing has done more […] to discredit cultural analysis than the construction of impeccable depictions of formal order in whose actual existence nobody can quite believe’108. When formal orders take precedence over substantive orders, the former end up being increasingly dissociated from the latter. What may make sense on paper may not make sense in real life (and vice versa). More importantly, what may make no sense on paper may make a lot of sense in real life (and vice versa). This insight places an enormous burden on the process (and purpose) of anthropological interpretation: ‘A good interpretation of anything […] takes us into the heart of that of which it is the interpretation.’109

Just as all cultures exist on a spectrum between coherence and incoherence, so do the interpretations by which they are sustained (‘from within’) and/or studied (‘from without’).

1.9 Culture and context

For Geertz, all interpretations (and misinterpretations) need to be put in context. They are, by definition, perspectival and ‘inherently inconclusive’110. Given the tentative nature of all interpretations, ‘[e]thnographic findings are not privileged, just particular’111. Their epistemic value, in other words, needs to be relativized (without therefore subscribing to relativism112): spatiotemporal contingency pervades the social world—including all interpretations generated, negotiated, and evaluated within it. Contingency permeates not only all ontologies of the social world but also the first- and second-order epistemologies that arise within it. The notion that ethnographic findings can rise above the contingency of the historical settings in which they emerge amounts to a transcendental illusion.

One of the most striking features of ‘the anthropologist’s findings is their complex specificness, their circumstantiality’113. There is no anthropology without a critical awareness of the situatedness at the core of all forms of sociality. Far from being reducible to an abstract principle of anthropological research, however, the methodological commitment to drawing on ‘material produced by long-term, mainly (though not exclusively) qualitative, highly participative, and almost obsessively fine-comb field study in confined contexts’114 is vital to the ethnographic enterprise. In fact, it is a precondition for developing and substantiating ‘the mega-concepts with which contemporary social science is afflicted’115 and which tend to be associated with macro-theoretical approaches—such as functionalism, systems theory, and complexity theory.

One of the many lessons that such a microscopic116 grassroots approach teaches us is that, unless social-scientific ‘mega-concepts’117 and grand theories are rooted in a fine-grained understanding of cultural dynamics and constellations as they emerge in everyday life, there is no chance of acquiring ‘the sort of sensible actuality that makes it possible to think not only realistically and concretely about them, but, what is more important, creatively and imaginatively with them’118. The methodological challenges raised by the microscopic analysis of ethnography are ‘both real and critical’119.

The point, however, is not to focus on micro-sociological settings with the aim of treating each of them as a mini-universe, reducible to a ‘world in a teacup’120 or ‘cloud chamber’121, let alone an autopoietic system. Rather, the point is to acknowledge that ‘social actions are comments on more than themselves’122, in the sense that they convey potentially significant meanings about both the microcosms (such as social fields, lifeworlds, and communities) and the macrocosms (such as social institutions, systems, and societies) in which they are spatiotemporally situated. ‘Small facts speak to large issues, winks to epistemology, or sheep raids to revolution, because they are made to.’123 It is not simply that small is beautiful but, rather, that small is relevant. Put differently, small is actually big because it is a foundational part of the bigger picture.

1.10 Culture and interpretation

A major limitation of interpretive approaches to different aspects of social life ‘is that they tend to resist, or to be permitted to resist, conceptual articulation and thus to escape systematic modes of assessment’124. This is not the case because—unlike explanation [Erklären]—interpretation or understanding [Verstehen] may be misconceived as an atheoretical, or even anti-theoretical, endeavour. Rather, this is the case because ‘[y]ou either grasp an interpretation or you do not, see the point of it or you do not, accept it or you do not’125. Interpretation is not merely a cognitive mechanism (subject to the laws of logic, validity, or rationality) but also an experiential and existential journey (contingent on different degrees of recognition, relevance, and resonance).

If an interpretation, however, is ‘[i]mprisoned in the immediacy of its own detail, it is presented as self-validating, or, worse, as validated by the supposedly developed sensitivities of the person who presents it’126. If, by contrast, it is open to being challenged by other interpretations and, hence, by access to details from outside its epistemic and/or experiential comfort zone, it stands a chance of being revised (and, ultimately, strengthened) by exposing its own limitations and incorporating insights from alternative perspectives. If anthropology—or any adjacent field of inquiry for that matter—claims to be a science, it should be able to demonstrate that ‘the conceptual structure of a cultural interpretation’127 is as solid, formulable, and ‘susceptible to explicit canons of appraisal’128 as the procedural norms and principles underlying experimental and observational methods in the natural sciences. And yet, the theoretical development of cultural interpretations is difficult for at least two reasons:

a.

There is ‘the need for theory to stay rather closer to the ground than tends to be the case in sciences more able to give themselves over to imaginative abstraction’129. The anthropological imagination is at its best when keeping its ‘flights of ratiocination’130 relatively short, thereby avoiding an ivory-tower scenario in which they ‘drift off into logical dreams, academic bemusements with formal symmetry’131 imposed upon, and essentially misrepresenting, social reality. ‘The whole point of a semiotic approach to culture is […] to aid us in gaining access to the conceptual world in which our subjects live so that we can, in some extended sense of the term, converse with them.’132

This interpretive mission requires anthropologists to take the subjects they study seriously and to regard them as knowledge-seeking entities capable of action and reflection. For this to be accomplished, cultural theory needs to recognize that ‘it is not its own master’133 but dependent on the realities whose complexities it is designed to capture. Since ‘it is unseverable from the immediacies thick description presents’134, its capacity to determine the course of its direction—and to do so ‘in terms of its internal logic’135—is limited, unless it purposively detaches itself from the cultural dynamics and constellations it is intended to comprehend.

Given its reliance on interpretation, cultural analysis is not a cumulative, let alone cumulativist, enterprise. ‘Rather than following a rising curve of cumulative findings, cultural analysis breaks up into a disconnected yet coherent sequence of bolder and bolder sorties.’136 Rather than seeking to get closer and closer to ‘the truth’, it aims to offer a perceptive account of the various truths competing within and between different cultural communities. According to this particularist, rather than universalist, understanding of cultural analysis, a ‘study is an advance if it is more incisive—whatever that may mean—than those that preceded it’137. It does not stand on the shoulders of previous studies; instead, it ‘runs by their side’138, challenging them, while itself being challenged by them.

Its interpretive outlook being antithetical to epistemic cumulativism, cultural analysis is hardly compatible with the modern ideal of conceptual system building. If ‘one looks for systematic treatises in the field, one is so soon disappointed, the more so if one finds any’139. To the extent that insightful conceptual frameworks cannot be abstracted from the empirical studies on which they are based, it is misleading to speak of ‘cultural theory’ in a narrow—that is, theoreticist—sense. To put it bluntly, cultural theory needs both theory and culture: the most sophisticated versions of the former remain empty unless they are empirically grounded in the latter.

‘Theoretical formulations hover so low over the interpretations they govern that they don’t make much sense or hold much interest apart from them.’140 While theoretical work and empirical work are deeply intertwined, their relationship is sustained by the mediating power of interpretation. To be clear, there is no theory without a degree of epistemic generalization. If theoretical generalizations are formulated ‘independently of their applications’141, however, ‘they seem either commonplace or vacant’142. Devoid of a strong connection between theoretical reflections and empirical investigations, interpretive anthropology—understood as an ethnographic undertaking—fails to live up to the standards of rigorous social-scientific research.

There is little point, then, in proposing a ‘General Theory of Cultural Interpretation’143, since it is not obvious what may be gained from such an endeavour. In the realm of cultural interpretation, ‘the essential task of theory building […] is not to codify abstract regularities but to make thick description possible, not to generalize across cases but to generalize within them’144. Ethnographic modes of generalization are case-specific, both in terms of the contexts from which they are derived and in terms of the claims they make about their applicability to different aspects of the social universe.

b.

At least in the strict meaning of the term, cultural theory is not predictive145. Indeed, the cultural interpretations on which cultural theories are founded are ‘merely post facto’146. The relationship between past and future is, of course, at stake in any form of theorizing. On the one hand, they build on findings, which—be definition—emanate from past experiences. On the other hand, they may make assertions about possible future developments, whose occurrence may be measured by probabilistic models. The former is common across a large variety of disciplinary fields of inquiry. The latter is more common in the natural sciences than in the social sciences and almost absent in the humanities. It would be erroneous, however, to conclude that cultural theory ‘has only to fit (or, more carefully, to generate cogent interpretations of) realities past; it has also to survive—intellectually survive—realities to come147. Cultural dynamics unfold on a continuum between past and future, and so do the interpretations seeking to make sense of them. The longer the shelf life of a particular theory, the more likely it is to have captured something of importance in an insightful and resonant fashion.

If a theory enjoys a long shelf life, this may be a sign not only of its intellectual originality and context-specific relevance but also of its capacity for epistemic refinement and context-transcending applicability148. Geertz’s reflections on the place of ‘theory’ in an interpretive science serve to illustrate another point: the classical distinction between ‘description’ and ‘explanation’, which plays a pivotal role in the experimental and observational sciences, finds its equivalent in the methodological differentiation between ‘inscription’ (‘thick description’) and ‘specification’ (‘diagnosis’), which is central to his own project. The former is concerned with ‘setting down the meaning particular social actions have for the actors whose actions they are’149; the latter is committed to elucidating ‘what the knowledge thus attained demonstrates about the society in which it is found and, beyond that, about social life as such’150. In the context of the former, the first-person perspective provides insights into understanding [verstehen] social life from the point of view of those immersed in it (thereby contributing to its material and symbolic construction) as participants; in the context of the latter, the third-person perspective provides insights into explaining [erklären] social life from the point of view of those examining it (thereby contributing to its ethnographic objectification) as observers.

Thus, we are confronted with a ‘double task’151: on the one hand, there is the task of uncovering ‘the conceptual structures that inform our subjects’ acts, the “said” of social discourse’152; on the other hand, there is the task of constructing ‘a system of analysis in whose terms what is generic to those structures, what belongs to them because they are what they are, will stand out against the other determinants of human behaviour’153. The former task relies on the experiential processes and communicative encounters taking place in people’s lifeworlds. The latter task aims to shed light on the extent to which behavioural and ideological patterns emerging from local settings may, or may not, be relevant to understanding cultural forms, including the historical contexts in which they are situated154.

In short, a key objective of ethnographic research is to ensure that its theoretical contributions are instrumental in providing ‘a vocabulary in which what symbolic action has to say about itself—that is, about the role of culture in human life—can be expressed’155. It is in this ethnographic spirit that theory operates in Geertz’s work in general and in the essays collected in The Interpretation of Cultures in particular156.

Geertz’s interpretive anthropology seeks to overcome counterproductive divisions—such as micro vs. macro, concrete vs. abstract, hermeneutic vs. systemic, bottom-up vs. top-down, and so forth. His semiotic approach demonstrates that social-scientific ‘mega-concepts’157 and grand theories are tenable only if they are grounded in microscopic analyses conducted as part of a ‘thick-description ethnography’158, which, owing to its embeddedness in everyday life, has the potential of ‘rendering mere occurrences scientifically eloquent’159 and, at the same time, widely accessible.

Such a framework makes it possible ‘to draw large conclusions from small, but very densely textured facts’160, and to make bold claims about the vital role of cultural dynamics in the emergence of forms of life, by evaluating them against the (often messy and multilayered) background of ‘complex specifics’161 permeating ordinary existence. As part of this commitment, interpretation ‘goes all the way down to the most immediate observational level’162—and, along with it, the theoretical framework upon which it depends and through which it is capable of articulating itself in a conceptually sophisticated, logically coherent, and epistemically valuable manner. Interpretive anthropology, therefore, is both a reconstructive and a phenomenological project: as a reconstructive project, it aims ‘to rework the pattern of social relationships’163; as a phenomenological project, it aims ‘to rearrange the coordinates of the experienced world’164. Both components are crucial to understanding that ‘[s]ociety’s forms are culture’s substance’165 and culture’s forms are society’s substance. There is no society without culture, just as there is no culture without society.

Cultural analysis is marked by a sense of incompleteness. It is not only ‘intrinsically incomplete’166 but also profoundly challenging: ‘the more deeply it goes the less complete it is’167. In a curious way, it is ‘a strange science’168, since it is motivated by a radical degree of scepticism about both the outside world and itself as a critical endeavour refusing to provide conclusive findings. Its most revealing, significant, and original propositions are often its most tentative, speculative, and uncertain reflections. Rather than pretending to have resolved the issue at hand, it is willing—and, indeed, eager—‘to intensify the suspicion’169 (that is, both its own and that of others), conceding that, possibly, it is ‘not quite getting it right’170 and stressing that this attitude defines the craft of ethnography.

To subscribe to ‘a semiotic concept of culture and an interpretive approach to the study of it’171 requires acknowledging that every ‘ethnographic assertion’172 is ‘essentially contestable’173. If there is such a thing as ‘progress’ in anthropology (including its interpretive variants), then it ‘is marked less by a perfection of consensus than by a refinement of debate’174. Owing to their discipline’s dialogical, rather than monological, orientation, interpretive anthropologists thrive by communicating not only with other researchers but also with the participants whose lives they are committed to studying. Given the experiential and epistemic value of such a simultaneously interpretive and participatory approach, it is no surprise that ‘the role of symbolic forms in human life’175 is taken seriously—not only by anthropologists but also by scholars from other disciplines across the humanities, social sciences, and natural sciences.

To be clear, emphasizing the symbolic dimensions of social life is not equivalent to ignoring, much less denying, the existential dilemmas with which meaning-seeking creatures are confronted while navigating the world. On the contrary, it means ‘to plunge into the midst of them’176 and to recognize that they are part of the human condition. ‘The essential vocation of interpretive anthropology is not to answer our deepest questions’177, as is the case with philosophy—notably in the areas of metaphysics, epistemology, logic, aesthetics, and ethics. Rather, its mission is ‘to make available to us answers that others […] have given, and thus to include them in the consuitable record of what man has said’178. Instead of tackling ‘the big questions’179 from the scholastic position of armchair philosophy, interpretive anthropology is committed to addressing existential (and seemingly trivial) issues by drawing on the experiences gained, and the knowledge generated, by ordinary people, capable of mobilizing their socially relevant (and culturally contingent) resources.

2 Critical Reflections

Having demonstrated that Geertz’s account of culture requires a systematic assessment of various crucial relationships, it makes sense to examine some controversial issues arising from his approach. Such a critical analysis of the limitations and shortcomings of Geertz’s framework is not meant to be a demolition exercise; rather, it aims to show that valuable lessons can be learnt from exploring the extent to which a range of analytical oppositions may be better understood as conceptual pairs, which are vital ingredients of critical social inquiry and which, as interdependent and complementary components, contribute to overcoming counterproductive divisions in the humanities and social sciences.

2.1 Between interpretation and explanation

In any ethnography, gathering background information180 is important for contextualizing one’s object of study. The challenge, however, consists in demonstrating the extent to which an interactional background—which comprises a combination of social, cultural, historical, and other dimensions—can be both interpreted in hermeneutic-phenomenological terms (in accordance with the paradigm of Verstehen) and explained in functionalist terms (in accordance with the paradigm of Erklären). Just as facts can be explained and meanings can be interpreted, meanings can be explained and facts can be interpreted. Both explanatory interpretations and interpretive explanations are integral parts of social science. Perhaps, the marriage of hermeneutics and functionalism is not so unhappy after all181.

2.2 Between the micro and the macro

Ethnographers face up to the challenge of absorbing the presence of individual and collective forces, which—as structural and agential variables that are ‘at once strange, irregular, and inexplicit’182—govern everyday life. A key question arising from this issue, however, is why some societies appear to be better (or worse) than others at reaching an equilibrium between their relatively stable, organized, and predictable dimensions, on the one hand, and their fragile, messy, and unpredictable dimensions, on the other. To account for the multi-level complexity of these dynamics, it is vital to combine micro-sociological (including ethnographic, hermeneutic, and phenomenological) with macro-sociological (including functionalist, systems-theoretic, and structuralist) perspectives.

2.3 Between the particular and the universal

It is one thing to draw attention to the tension between the particular and the universal in terms of the relationship between ‘[t]he great natural variation of cultural forms’183 and ‘the biological unity of the human species’184. It is quite another to resolve this tension—or at least to illustrate how the former can be squared with the latter. Paradoxically, particularity and universality represent two co-constitutive elements of the human condition. To be clear, universals may manifest themselves in particular ways, just as particulars may amount to expressions of universal features. Culture is both ‘a particular universal’ and ‘a universal particular’: insofar as it is present in all forms of life, culture constitutes ‘a particular universal’ of human existence; insofar as different forms of life generate different modes of being, culture constitutes ‘a universal particular’ separating human collectives—in terms of their values, habits, conventions, traditions, and codes of conduct—from one another.

2.4 Between reality and representation

‘The ethnographer “inscribes” social discourse’185 and, hence, ‘writes it down186. Thus, the ethnographic engagement with reality is discursive in a twofold manner: it reconstructs the discursive constitution of social life (object of study), and it accomplishes this in a discursive fashion (method of study). Faced with this task, the ethnographer must avoid confusing the reality of representation with the representation of reality187. If reality is reduced to its textual, discursive, subjective, normative, psychological, and/or ideological construction, then we run the risk of falling into the traps of textualism, discursivism, subjectivism, normativism, psychologism, and/or ideologism. While there is more to the construction of human reality than its material, physical, and empirical dimensions, there is more to it than its nonmaterial, nonphysical, and nonempirical counterparts.

2.5 Between nature and culture

In anthropology, the concept of culture is of paramount importance. Given the pivotal role it plays in the construction of both human and nonhuman realities, it occupies a central place not only in the humanities and social sciences but also in the natural sciences. It is no accident, therefore, that the empirical and conceptual boundaries between ‘nature’ and ‘culture’ are increasingly blurred. If we accept that human (and some nonhuman) actors exist on a continuum between ‘nature’ and ‘culture’, we need to ask to what extent this distinction still holds true, on both empirical and conceptual grounds.

2.6 Between interpretations of culture and cultures of interpretation

It is, of course, prudent to reject reductive conceptions of culture (whether these be cognitivist, subjectivist, formalist, behaviourist, idealist, or otherwise). A first step towards overcoming their respective shortcomings is to provide a high-resolution approach capable of differentiating discipline-specific perspectives on culture:

  • In anthropology, the concept of culture commonly refers to a set of symbolically mediated behaviours and ideas acquired by human beings as members of forms of life188.

  • In philosophy, the concept of culture is crucial on at least three levels: (a) ontologically, as an existential source of species-constitutive transcendence; (b) epistemologically, as a vehicle allowing for symbolic meditation and interpretation; (c) ethically, as a locus of normative regulation189.

  • In sociology, the concept of culture has acquired, and been studied in terms of, several meanings: (a) in cultural sociology, as the performative nucleus of social constructions; (b) in economic sociology, as a commodity; (c) in digital sociology, as a hyperreality; (d) in critical sociology, as an interest- and power-laden field of competition and struggle; (e) in political sociology, as an arena of ideas, beliefs, norms, and values190.

  • In the arts, the concept of culture describes a source of aesthetic experience191.

  • In politics, the concept of culture has, especially in recent decades, acquired the meaning of a relationally constructed and power-laden sphere, which has the characteristics of a social battlefield192.

Granted, this is by no means an exhaustive overview of seminal interpretations of culture193. It illustrates, however, that a nuanced understanding of culture is needed, if one aims to grasp the principal functions it plays in the construction of reality, including its constitutive (notably social, linguistic, political, ideological, religious, economic, demographic, and other) dimensions194.

2.7 Between cognitive orders and normative orders

The cognitivist or mentalist notion that culture is located ‘in the minds and hearts of men’195 is one-sided and flawed in that it fails to account for the multiple factors at play in the construction of codified behaviour, which is indispensable to the emergence of more or less viable and solidified forms of social interaction. Granted, cognitivist and mentalist conceptions of culture have received considerable attention in the contemporary social sciences—including in anthropology196 and sociology197. One of the main challenges in this respect concerns the question of the extent to which neuroscientific approaches can be combined with their social-scientific counterparts, especially with regard to explanatory models on culturally variable patterns of socialization198.

Ultimately, however, every ‘cultural order’ is a ‘normative order’199—that is, an order within which behaviour is (implicitly or explicitly) codified, in accordance with (implicit or explicit) conventions, standards, values, assumptions, and principles. To be empirically relevant, these need to be imprinted in our bodies in general and our brains in particular. There are no culturally defined modes of being without internalized schemes of perception, interpretation, appreciation, and action (and vice versa). In brief, there are no ‘normative orders’ without ‘cognitive orders’, just as there are no ‘cognitive orders’ without ‘normative orders’.

2.8 Between the public and the private

While it is true that ‘[c]ulture is public because meaning is’200 (and the same applies to language201), it is also true that every culture comprises private dimensions (just as every language does), expressed in private meanings. To be sure, the Wittgensteinian critique of ‘the private language argument’202 may be as persuasive as the Adornian thesis of ‘the preponderance of the object’203.

A key question is why—to a greater or lesser degree—the tension between ‘public’ and ‘private’ (and, by implication, between ‘public interests’ and ‘private interests’)204 pervades all forms of life: ‘individualist’ or ‘collectivist’, ‘complex’ or ‘simple’, ‘loose’ or ‘tight’, ‘vertical’ or ‘horizontal’, ‘freedom-based’ or ‘control-based’, ‘person-centred’ or ‘community-centred’, ‘relatively heterogeneous’ or ‘relatively homogeneous’, ‘technologically advanced’ or ‘technologically backward’, ‘large-scale’ or ‘small-scale’205.

Another crucial question is where to draw the line between ‘public’ and ‘private’, both analytically (in anthropological and sociological terms) and normatively (in moral and political terms). Different analytical frameworks (from hermeneutics and phenomenology to functionalism and systems theory) and different normative frameworks (from virtue ethics, deontological ethics, and utilitarian ethics to moral sentimentalism and the ethics of care—from anarchism, communism, and socialism to liberalism, conservatism, and fascism—from feminism to environmentalism) will provide different answers to this question. Both theoretically and practically, the public/private dichotomy means different things to different people (from different cultural backgrounds and with different worldviews).

2.9 Between common humanity and cultural diversity

One need not be a professional anthropologist to comprehend that a person from one culture may perceive a person from another culture as ‘a complete enigma’206 (and vice versa). When this happens, they experience the full force of cultural (and often linguistic) incommensurability and face the consequences of interpretive inaccessibility. Casting doubt on the received wisdom of some scholars (notably those pursuing postmodern and/or poststructuralist agendas), it is important to recognize that, even in cases of seemingly insurmountable degrees of cultural incommensurability and/or interpretive inaccessibility, there are cross- and transcultural channels of communication between actors, permitting them to engage with, to relate to, and to make sense of each other207. Their common humanity transcends all (real or imagined) obstacles created by cultural (including linguistic) diversity.

2.10 Between ordinary knowledge and scientific knowledge

There would be no point in pursuing social science (including interpretive anthropology) if, as researchers, we did not aspire to go beyond the epistemic realm of everyday preconceptions. In order to undertake this ‘epistemo­logical break’208, we need to draw a distinction between ordinary knowledge (generated and used by laypersons) and scientific knowledge (produced and employed by researchers and experts). Considering the distinction between ‘ordinary knowledge’ and ‘scientific knowledge’, we are confronted with three main options209:

  • Option 1: The former is superior to the latter, because it is based on the ‘genuine’ (individual and/or collective) experiences of human actors in ‘real life’. On this view, the former provides a degree of per­spectival authenticity that the latter, due to its socially detached constitution, fails to embrace, let alone to convey.

  • Option 2: The latter is superior to the former, because it is—at once—empirically substantiated, meth­odologically rigorous, epistemologically reflexive, terminologically precise, and theoretically informed. On this view, the latter guarantees a degree of epistemic certainty that the former, owing to its inevitable reliance on everyday preconceptions, fails to strive for, let alone to achieve.

  • Option 3: Little is to be gained from constructing a rigid epistemic hierarchy between the former and the latter. Although ‘ordinary knowledge’ and ‘scientific knowledge’ are qualitatively different, they reflect equally legitimate types of epistemic engagement with the world. Rather than opposing ‘ordinary’ and ‘scientific’ ways of attributing meaning to and acting upon reality, we should seek to cross-fertilize these—arguably complementary—modes of relating to the world. As laypersons, we can navigate our everyday lives and—whether we do so consciously or unconsciously—draw on scientif­ically established insights. As experts, we can study objective, normative, and/or subjective aspects of the world and take ordinary people—including their conceptions, as well as their misconceptions, of reality—seriously.

Based on a sound understanding of the relationship between ‘ordinary knowledge’ and ‘scientific knowledge’, interpretive anthropology should commit to the third option. Whether we focus on the sociology of knowledge, the sociology of everyday life, the sociology of morality, the sociology of science and technology, or any other relevant area of sociological inquiry, Geertz’s interpretive anthropology serves as a source of critical insight for each of them: in all realms of life—whether these be represented in, shaped by, and/or constructed through ordinary or scientific discourses—humans are caught in webs of significance, which they produce, reproduce, and potentially transform through their actions and interactions as well as their classifications and interpretations.

2.11 Between correlation and causation

From a semiotic perspective, culture is not reducible to an anonymous power or force, capable of colonizing both the material and the symbolic dimensions of our existence in a causalist fashion. Given its emphasis on the multi-level and multi-agential constitution of social reality, interpretive anthropology rejects both causalist and determinist explanatory frameworks. In accordance with this view, we must avoid lapsing into the correlation–causation fallacy—that is, we cannot deduce a cause-and-effect relationship between two (or more) developments from an observed correlation between them. The dictum ‘correlation does not imply causation’, although it has almost become a truism in the social sciences, needs to be defended to prevent us from being seduced by simplistic explanations of multilayered, multifaceted, and multifactorial states of affairs and events. Interpretive anthropology should admit, however, that it is not always clear where to draw the line between causation and correlation—not least because, in some cases, our culture may cause us to behave and/or to think in a particular way (and not in another).

2.12 Between familiarity and strangeness

The old cliché that anthropology is all about making the familiar strange and the strange familiar persists to this day. Arguably, this laudable mission is transferable to other academic disciplines. Scientific endeavours that succeed in shedding light on the underlying forces that escape our common-sense perception of reality make the unfamiliar familiar. Scientific endeavours that succeed in challenging and breaking free from everyday preconceptions of reality make the familiar unfamiliar. Even if we recognize, however, that both tasks are essential to the pursuit of a critical social science, we need to concede that, in many cases, the distinction between ‘the familiar’ and ‘the unfamiliar’ is not as straightforward as it may appear at first glance. Social life comprises grey areas, which both ordinary actors and researchers may experience and conceptualize as ‘semi-familiar’ (or ‘semi-unfamiliar’, depending on one’s angle). Arguably, both those immersed in everyday life and those studying everyday life can learn a great deal from these grey areas, not least because they illustrate that interpretive processes—both for ‘insiders’ and for ‘outsiders’—can be marked by high degrees of elasticity, ambiguity, and uncertainty.

2.13 Between ontology and epistemology

In any scientific investigation, it makes sense to draw a distinction between ontology and methodology, implying that ‘the object of study is one thing and the study of it another’210. This insight, however, requires a further consideration, which concerns the realm of epistemology, including its role in anthropology: the normativity of the perspective sets the parameters for the descriptibility of the object211. Ethnographers, even when making a conscious and sustained effort to minimize their implicit biases, carry their preconceptions into their fieldwork. The most reflexive anthropologists cannot remove the projective power of perspective-, meaning-, and value-laden assumptions from their interpretations212.

2.14 Between functionalism and interpretivism

It would be naïve to deny that ‘[c]ultural systems must have a minimal degree of coherence’213, since social life is not viable unless it is relatively stable, organized, and predictable. To the extent that interpretive anthropology acknowledges the fact that society is unthinkable without its reliance on cultural systems, it is predicated on a functionalist understanding of the structural preconditions for the emergence and sustainability of forms of life. Rather than stressing only its ethnographic orientation, however, interpretive anthropology should be upfront about its subjacent functionalist presuppositions. It is no accident that, in the secondary literature, there has been a growing interest in studying the links between functionalist and interpretive approaches. More specifically, there have been promising attempts at examining the theoretical and methodological implications of Geertz’s exposure to, engagement with, and training in functionalist modes of analysis for his interpretive approach214.

2.15 Between Feldanschauung and Weltanschauung

Language games obtain their existential significance from the fact that they are—at once—manifestations, vehicles, and engines of forms of life. Interpretive anthropology would benefit from combining this Wittgensteinian insight into the relationship between ‘forms of life’ and ‘language games’ with Bourdieusian inquiries into the relationship between ‘social fields’ and ‘illusio’. Each social microcosm generates a field-specific view of the world [Feldanschauung]215. The problematic irony of illusio consists in its power to convert the subject’s Feldanschauung into its Weltanschauung.

Be it in the economic field (‘business is business’), the artistic field (‘art for the sake of art’), the judicial field (‘justice for the sake of justice’), or the scientific field (‘truth for the sake of truth’)216—every social field generates its own set of competing discourses, mobilized by its participants not only to pursue their strategies and interests but also, in a more fundamental sense, to attach meaning to the world. Their encounter with the world [Weltbegegnung] strives for an interpretation of the world [Weltdeutung]. How they interpret the world is substantially conditioned by the positions they occupy, and the dispositions they acquire, in the world as social actors: their Weltanschauung is necessarily a form of Feldanschauung217. That they interpret the world is due to their place in the world as human beings: their Weltinterpretation218 stems from their Bedeutungsbedürfnis219. Interpretive anthropology can shed light on both the species-constitutive and the species-divisive functions of interpretation. Whereas the former are field-transcendent, the latter are field-contingent.

In short, valuable lessons can be learnt from cross-fertilizing Geertz’s interpretive anthropology (notably in relation to the meaning-generating functions provided by culturally codified webs of significance) with Habermas’s critical theory (notably in relation to the species-constitutive potential inherent in communicative action) and Bourdieu’s reflexive sociology (notably in relation to the species-divisive power of competing and asymmetrically structured fields)220.

Conclusion

The preceding analysis has aimed to demonstrate that the key conceptual components of Geertz’s enterprise can be located in his case for an interpretive theory of culture, epitomized in the methodological commitment to providing a ‘thick description’. The first part has examined the core assumptions underlying Geertz’s defence of this endeavour, whereas the second part has offered a discussion of some controversial issues arising from his approach.

In relation to the first task, this paper has argued that Geertz’s account of culture requires a systematic assessment of various crucial relationships: (1) culture and ‘thick description’, (2) culture and ethnography, (3) culture and anthropology, (4) culture and meaning, (5) culture and (un)familiarity, (6) culture and science, (7) culture and semiotics, (8) culture and coherence, (9) culture and context, and (10) culture and interpretation. As illustrated above, the thorough examination of these dimensions makes it clear that Geertz’s account of culture is far more nuanced than a catch-all summary may suggest.

In relation to the second task, this paper has cast light on contentious matters arising from Geertz’s perspective, positing that valuable lessons can be learnt from exploring the extent to which a range of analytical oppositions may be better understood as conceptual pairs, which are vital ingredients of critical social inquiry and which, as interdependent and complementary components, contribute to overcoming counterproductive divisions in the humanities and social sciences: (1) interpretation and explanation, (2) the micro and the macro, (3) the particular and the universal, (4) reality and representation, (5) nature and culture, (6) interpretations of culture and cultures of interpretation, (7) cognitive orders and normative orders, (8) the public and the private, (9) common humanity and cultural diversity, (10) ordinary knowledge and scientific knowledge, (11) correlation and causation, (12) familiarity and strangeness, (13) ontology and epistemology, (14) functionalism and interpretivism, and (15) Feldanschauung and Weltanschauung.

Having considered both the contributions and the limitations of Geertz’s framework, it becomes possible not only to appreciate the theoretical and practical challenges involved in the interpretation of cultures but also to grasp the significance of the conceptual pairs that are essential for pursuing fruitful and imaginative forms of critical social research. Irrespective of one’s view of Geertz’s approach, there can be no doubt that—as shown above—his case for an interpretive anthropology continues to be not only largely persuasive but also highly relevant to the humanities and social sciences in the 21st century.

References

Adorno, T.W. (1973). Negative Dialectics (E.B. Ashton, Trans.). London: Routledge. (Original work published 1966)

Alcoff, L.M. (Eds.). (1998). Epistemology: The Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell.

Apel, K. (1984). Understanding and Explanation: A Transcendental-Pragmatic Perspective (G. Warnke, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Original work published 1979)

Archer, M. (2007). Making Our Way Through the World: Human Reflexivity and Social Mobility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511618932

Baert, P. (2003). Pragmatism, Realism and Hermeneutics. Foundations of Science, 8(1), 89–106. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1022445814115

Baert, P. (2005). Max Weber’s Interpretative Method. In P. Baert, Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Towards Pragmatism (pp. 37–60). Cambridge: Polity.

Baggini, J. (2012). Ethics: The Big Questions. London: Quercus.

Bailey, J. (2000). Some Meanings of ‘the Private’ in Sociological Thought. Sociology, 34(3), 381–402. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0038038500000250

Barnard, H. (1990). Bourdieu and Ethnography: Reflexivity, Politics and Praxis. In R. Harker, C. Mahar, & C. Wilkes (Eds.), An Introduction to the Work of Pierre Bourdieu: The Practice of Theory (pp. 58–85). Basingstoke: Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-21134-0_3

Beller, S., Bender, A., & Medin, D.L. (2012). Should Anthropology Be Part of Cognitive Science? Topics in Cognitive Science, 4(3), 342–353. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1756-8765.2012.01196.x

Bender, A., & Beller, S. (2015). The Mutual Challenge of Anthropology and Cognitive Science. Social Anthropology, 23(2), 199–200. https://doi.org/10.1111/1469-8676.12116

Berger, P.L., & Luckmann, T. (1967). The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. London: Penguin. (Original work published 1966)

Blackburn, S. (2009). The Big Questions: Philosophy. London: Quercus.

Bloch, M. (2012). Anthropology and the Cognitive Challenge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bohman, J. (1997). Reflexivity, Agency and Constraint: The Paradoxes of Bourdieu’s Sociology of Knowledge. Social Epistemology, 11(2), 171–186. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691729708578841

Boltanski, L., & Thévenot, L. (2000). The Reality of Moral Expectations: A Sociology of Situated Judgement. Philosophical Explorations, 3(3), 208–231. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869790008523332

Bourdieu, P. (1980). Le sens pratique. Paris: Minuit.

Bourdieu, P. (1993). Comprendre. In P. Bourdieu (Eds.), La misère du monde (pp. 1389–1447). Paris: Seuil.

Bourdieu, P. (1997). Méditations pascaliennes. Paris: Seuil.

Bourdieu, P. (1998). La domination masculine. Paris: Seuil.

Bourdieu, P. (1999). Scattered Remarks. European Journal of Social Theory, 2(3), 333–340. https://doi.org/10.1177/13684319922224563

Bourdieu, P. (2004). Science of Science and Reflexivity (R. Nice, Trans). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 2001)

Bourdieu, P., & Eagleton, T. (1992). Doxa and Common Life. New Left Review, 191, 111–121.

Bourdieu, P., Schultheis, F., & Pfeuffer, A. (2011). With Weber against Weber: In Conversation with Pierre Bourdieu. In S. Susen & B.S. Turner (Eds.), The Legacy of Pierre Bourdieu (S. Susen, Trans) (pp. 111–124). London: Anthem Press. (Original work published 1999–2000)

Bourdieu, P., & Wacquant, L. (1992a). Language, Gender, and Symbolic Violence. In P. Bourdieu & L. Wacquant, An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology (pp. 140–174). Cambridge: Polity.

Bourdieu, P. & Wacquant, L. (1992b). The Personal is Social. In P. Bourdieu & L. Wacquant, An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology (pp. 202–215). Cambridge: Polity.

Bouvier, A. (2007). An Argumentativist Point of View in Cognitive Sociology. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 465–480. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368431007080707

Brekhus, W.H., & Ignatow, G. (Eds.). (2019). The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Brown, P. (2006). Cognitive Anthropology. In C. Jourdan & K. Tuite (Eds.), Language, Culture, and Society: Key Topics in Linguistic Anthropology (pp. 96–114). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Burkitt, I. (1997). The Situated Social Scientist: Reflexivity and Perspective in the Sociology of Knowledge. Social Epistemology, 11(2), 193–202. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691729708578843

Butt, T., & Langdridge, D. (2003). The Construction of Self: The Public Reach into the Private Sphere. Sociology, 37(3), 477–492. https://doi.org/10.1177/00380385030373005

Carey, S. (2015). The Science of Cognitive Science. Social Anthropology, 23(2), 204–207. https://doi.org/10.1111/1469-8676.12119

Cavell, S. (2002). Must We Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays (Updated ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1969)

Celikates, R. (2018). Critique as Social Practice: Critical Theory and Social Self-Understanding (N. van Steenbergen, Trans). London: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. (Original work published 2009)

Cerulo, K.A. (2010). Mining the Intersections of Cognitive Sociology and Neuroscience. Poetics, 38(2), 115–132. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.poetic.2009.11.005

Chernilo, D. (2017). Debating Humanity. Towards a Philosophical Sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Cicourel, A.V. (1974). Cognitive Sociology: Language and Meaning in Social Interaction. New York, NY: Free Press.

Collier, D., Hidalgo, F.D., & Maciuceanu, A.O. (2006). Essentially Contested Concepts: Debates and Applications. Journal of Political Ideologies, 11(3), 211–246. https://doi.org/10.1080/13569310600923782

Condren, C. (2009). Public, Private and the Idea of the ‘Public Sphere’ in Early-modern England. Intellectual History Review, 19(1), 15–28. https://doi.org/10.1080/17496970902722866

Cossu, A. (2021). Clifford Geertz, Intellectual Autonomy, and Interpretive Social Science. American Journal of Cultural Sociology, 9(3), 347–375. https://doi.org/10.1057/s41290-019-00085-8

Cossu, A. (2022). Talcott Parsons and Clifford Geertz: Modernization, Functionalism, and Interpretive Social Science. In A. Javier Treviño & H. Staubmann (Eds.), The Routledge International Handbook of Talcott Parsons Studies (pp. 261–270). London: Routledge.

Crouch, C. (2016). The Knowledge Corrupters: Hidden Consequences of the Financial Takeover of Public Life. Cambridge: Polity.

Cutler, A.C. (1997). Artifice, Ideology and Paradox: The Public/Private Distinction in International Law. Review of International Political Economy, 4(2), 261–285. https://doi.org/10.1080/096922997347788

D’Andrade, R.G. (1995). The Development of Cognitive Anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Dallmayr, F.R., & McCarthy, T.A. (Eds.). (1977). Understanding and Social Inquiry. South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

Dilthey, W. (1883). Einleitung in die Geisteswissenschaften. Versuch einer Grundlegung für das Studium der Gesellschaft und der Geschichte, Vol. 1. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

DiMaggio, P. (1997). Culture and Cognition. Annual Review of Sociology, 23, 263–287. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.soc.23.1.263

Dunaj, L., & Mertel, K.C.M. (Eds.). (2022). Hans-Herbert Kögler’s Critical Hermeneutics. London: Bloomsbury.

Eder, K. (2007). Cognitive Sociology and the Theory of Communicative Action: The Role of Communication and Language in the Making of the Social Bond. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 389–408. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368431007080702

Einstein, A. (1934). On the Method of Theoretical Physics. Philosophy of Science, 1(2), 163–169. https://doi.org/10.1086/286316

Floyd, J. (2020). Wittgenstein on Ethics: Working through Lebensformen. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 46(2), 115–130. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453718810918

Forst, R. (2002). Contexts of Justice: Political Philosophy beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism (J.M.M. Farrell, Trans). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. (Original work published 1994)

Forst, R.(2012). The Right to Justification. Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice (J. Flynn, Trans.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press. (Original work published 2007)

Forst, R. (2013a). Zum Begriff eines Rechtfertigungsnarrativs. In A. Fahrmeir (Ed.), Rechtfertigungsnarrative. Zur Begründung normativer Ordnung durch Erzählungen (pp. 11–28). Frankfurt am Main: Campus.

Forst, R. (2013b). Toleration in Conflict: Past and Present (C. Cronin, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 2003)

Forst, R. (2013c). Justification and Critique. Towards a Critical Theory of Politics (C. Cronin, Trans). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 2011)

Forst, R. (2014). Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue. London: Bloomsbury.

Forst, R. (2015a). Normativität und Macht. Zur Analyse sozialer Rechtfertigungsordnungen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

Forst, R.(2015b). Noumenal Power. Journal of Political Philosophy, 23(2), 111–127. https://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12046

Forst, R. (2017). Noumenal Alienation: Rousseau, Kant and Marx on the Dialectics of Self-Determination. Kantian Review, 22(4), 523–551. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1369415417000267

Forst, R., & Günther, K. (Eds.). (2011a). Die Herausbildung normativer Ordnungen. Interdisziplinäre Perspektiven. Frankfurt: Campus.

Forst, R., & Günther, K. (2011b). Die Herausbildung normativer Ordnungen. In R. Forst & K. Günther (Eds.), Die Herausbildung normativer Ordnungen. Interdisziplinäre Perspektiven (pp. 11–30). Frankfurt: Campus.

Forst, R., Hartmann, M., Jaeggi, R., & Saar, M. (Eds.). (2009). Sozialphilosophie und Kritik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Gallie, W.B. (1955). Essentially Contested Concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 167–198. https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/56.1.167

Geertz, C. (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays. New York, NY: Basic Books.

Geertz, C. (1984). Distinguished Lecture: Anti Anti-Relativism. American Anthropologist, 86(2), 263–278. https://doi.org/10.1525/aa.1984.86.2.02a00030

Geertz, C. (1988). Works and Lives: The Anthropologist as Author. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Geertz, C. (2000). Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology (3rd ed.). New York, NY: Basic Books. (Original work published 1983)

Geuss, R. (2001). Public Goods, Private Goods. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Goodenough, W.H. (1981). Culture, Language and Society (2nd ed.). Menlo Park, CA: Benjamin/Cummings. (Original work published 1971)

Goodenough, W.H. (2006). Description and Comparison in Cultural Anthropology. New Brunswick, NJ: AldineTransaction. (Original work published 1970)

Habermas, J. (1962). Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit: Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Habermas, J. (1987). The Problem of Understanding Meaning in the Social Sciences. In J. Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action. Volume 1: Reason and the Rationalization of Society (T. McCarthy, Trans.) (pp. 102–141). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 1981)

Habermas, J. (1989). The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society (T. Burger & F. Lawrence, Trans.). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 1962)

Habermas, J. (2001). From a Constitutive Theory to a Communicative Theory of Society (Sellars and Wittgenstein): Communicative and Cognitive Uses of Language. In J. Habermas, On the Pragmatics of Social Interaction: Preliminary Studies in the Theory of Communicative Action (B. Fultner, Trans.) (pp. 45–65). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 1984)

Habermas, J. (2003). The Future of Human Nature (H. Beister, M. Pensky, & W. Rehg, Trans.). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 2001)

Honneth, A., & Joas, H. (1988). Social Action and Human Nature (R. Meyer, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1980)

Hunter, J.F.M. (1968). ‘Forms of Life’ in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. American Philosophical Quarterly, 5(4), 233–243.

Hurley, S., & Chater, N. (Eds.). (2005). Perspectives on Imitation: From Neuroscience to Social Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/5331.001.0001

Husserl, E. (1970). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy (D. Carr, Trans.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. (Original work published 1954)

Husserl, E. (2001). Logical Investigations (J.N. Findlay, Trans.). London: Routledge. (Original work published 1900/1901)

Husserl, E. (2012). Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology (W.R. Boyce Gibson, Trans.). London: Routledge. (Original work published 1913/1931)

Ingold, T. (2015). Human Cognition is Intrinsically Social, Developmental and Historical. Social Anthropology, 23(2), 188–191. https://doi.org/10.1111/1469-8676.12112

Joas, H. (1991). The Unhappy Marriage of Hermeneutics and Functionalism. In A. Honneth & H. Joas (Eds.), Communicative Action: Essays on Jürgen Habermas’s ‘The Theory of Communicative Action’ (J. Gaines and D.L. Jones, Trans.) (pp. 97–118). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 1986)

Kant, I. (1995). Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Wilhelm Weischedel, ed.). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. (Original work published 1781)

Kaufmann, L., & Clément, F. (2015). Must Cognitive Anthropology Be Mentalistic? Moving towards a Relational Ontology of Social Reality. Social Anthropology, 23(2), 201–203. https://doi.org/10.1111/1469-8676.12118

Keesing, R.M. (1974). Theories of Culture. Annual Review of Anthropology, 3, 73–97. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.an.03.100174.000445

Keller, D.R. (Eds.). (2010). Environmental Ethics: The Big Questions. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

Kluckhohn, C. (1949). Mirror for Man: The Relation of Anthropology to Modern Life. New York, NY: McGraw Hill.

Kögler, H. (1996). The Self-Empowered Subject: Habermas, Foucault and Hermeneutic Reflexivity. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 22(4), 13–44. https://doi.org/10.1177/019145379602200402

Kögler, H. (1996). The Power of Dialogue: Critical Hermeneutics after Gadamer and Foucault (P. Hendrickson, Trans). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Original work published 1992)

Kögler, H., & Stueber, K.R. (Eds.). (2000). Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

Korsmeyer, C. (Eds.). (1998). Aesthetics: The Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell.

Kripke, S.A. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Oxford: Blackwell.

Kurasawa, F. (2003). Prolegomena to an Intercultural Critical Theory. Current Perspectives in Social Theory, 22, 325–348. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0278-1204(03)80015-4

Lakatos, I., Feyerabend, P., & Motterlini, M. (1999). For and Against Method: Including Lakatos's Lectures on Scientific Method and the Lakatos-Feyerabend Correspondence. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Langer, S.K. (1942). Philosophy in a New Key: A Study in the Symbolism of Reason, Rite, and Art. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Laudan, L. (1983). The Demise of the Demarcation Problem. In R.S. Cohen & L. Laudan (Eds.), Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis: Essays in Honor of Adolf Grünbaum (pp. 111–127). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

Lloyd, G.E.R. (1983). Science, Folklore and Ideology: Studies in the Life Sciences in Ancient Greece. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Marston, S.A. (1995). The Private Goes Public: Citizenship and the New Spaces of Civil Society. Political Geography, 14(2), 194–198. https://doi.org/10.1016/0962-6298(95)91665-Q

Morgan, A. (2017). A Preponderance of Objects: Critical Theory and the Turn to the Object. Adorno Studies, 1(1), 13–30. http://adornostudies.org/ojs/index.php/as/article/view/3

Nye, A. (Eds.). (1998). Philosophy of Language: The Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Oberst, M. (2015). Two Worlds and Two Aspects: On Kant’s Distinction between Things in Themselves and Appearances. Kantian Review, 20(1), 53–75. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1369415414000284

Outhwaite, W. (1986). Understanding Social Life: The Method Called Verstehen (2nd ed.). Lewes: Jean Stroud. (Original work published 1975)

Outhwaite, W. (2000). Rekonstruktion und methodologischer Dualismus. In S. Müller-Doohm (Ed.), Das Interesse der Vernunft: Rückblicke auf das Werk von Jürgen Habermas seit ‘Erkenntnis und Interesse’ (pp. 218–241). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Pharo, P. (2007). How is Sociological Realism Possible? Sociology after Cognitive Science. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 481–496. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368431007080708

Pinker, S. (2002). The Blank Slate. The Modern Denial of Human Nature. London: Allen Lane.

Powell, W.W., & Clemens, E.S. (Eds.). (1998). Private Action and the Public Good. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Regnier, D., & Astuti, R. (2015). Introduction: Taking up the Cognitive Challenge. Social Anthropology, 23(2), 131–134. https://doi.org/10.1111/1469-8676.12117

Resnik, D.B. (2000). A Pragmatic Approach to the Demarcation Problem. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 31(2), 249–267. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0039-3681(00)00004-2

Robbins, D. (1998). The Need for an Epistemological ‘Break’. In M. Grenfell & D. James, Bourdieu and Education: Acts of Practical Theory (pp. 27–51). London: Falmer Press.

Roitblat, H.L., Herman, L.M., & Nachtigall , P.E. (Eds.). (1993). Language and Communication: Comparative Perspectives. Comparative Cognition and Neuroscience Series. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Rosa, H. (2020). The Uncontrollability of the World (J.C. Wagner, Trans.). Cambridge: Polity. (Original work published 2018)

Ryle, G. (2009). Collected Papers. Volume 2, Collected Essays 1929–1968. London: Routledge. (Original work published 1971)

Salmerón Castro, F.I. (2002). Modernidad y prácticas políticas: democracia, eslabonamientos y mediaciones en la sociedad civil. Revista Mexicana de Sociología, 64(1), 31–65. https://doi.org/10.2307/3541480

Sewell, W.H, Jr. (1999). The Concept(s) of Culture. In V.E. Bonnell, L. Hunt, & R. Biernacki (Eds.), Beyond the Cultural Turn: New Directions in the Study of Society and Culture (pp. 35–61). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Sherratt, T.N., & Wilkinson, D.M. (2009). Big Questions in Ecology and Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Solomon, R.C., & Higgins, K.M. (2014). The Big Questions: A Short Introduction to Philosophy (9th International ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. (Original work published 1994)

Steinberger, P.J. (1999). Public and Private. Political Studies, 47(2), 292–313. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9248.00201

Sterba, J.P. (Eds.). (2009). Ethics: The Big Questions (2nd ed.). Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. (Original work published 1998)

Strauss, C. (2006). Cognitive Anthropology. In K. Brown (Eds.) Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (2nd ed.) (pp. 529–532). Oxford: Elsevier. https://doi.org/10.1016/B0-08-044854-2/03016-9

Strydom, P. (2007). Introduction: A Cartography of Contemporary Cognitive Social Theory. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 339–356. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368431007080699

Strydom, P. (2015). The Latent Cognitive Sociology in Habermas: Extrapolated from Between Facts and Norms. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 41(3), 273–291. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453714563877

Stump, E., & Murray, M.J. (Eds.). (1999). Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell.

Susen, S. (2007). The Foundations of the Social: Between Critical Theory and Reflexive Sociology. Oxford: Bardwell Press.

Susen, S. (2010). Meadian Reflections on the Existential Ambivalence of Human Selfhood. Studies in Social and Political Thought, 17, 62–81. https://ssrn.com/abstract=1700179

Susen, S. (2011a). Bourdieu and Adorno on the Transformation of Culture in Modern Society: Towards a Critical Theory of Cultural Production. In S. Susen & B.S. Turner (Eds.), The Legacy of Pierre Bourdieu: Critical Essays (pp. 173–202). London: Anthem Press. https://doi.org/10.7135/UPO9780857289278.009

Susen, S. (2011b). Critical Notes on Habermas's Theory of the Public Sphere. Sociological Analysis, 5(1), 37–62. https://ssrn.com/abstract=2043824

Susen, S. (2012). ‘Open Marxism’ against and beyond the ‘Great Enclosure’? Reflections on How (Not) to Crack Capitalism. Journal of Classical Sociology, 12(2), 281–331. https://doi.org/10.1177/1468795X12443547

Susen, S. (2013a). Comments on Patrick Baert and Filipe Carreira da Silva’s Social Theory in the Twentieth Century and Beyond. Towards a ‘Hermeneutics-Inspired Pragmatism’? Distinktion: Scandinavian Journal of Social Theory, 14(1), 80–101. https://doi.org/10.1080/1600910X.2012.690772

Susen, S. (2013b). Bourdieusian Reflections on Language: Unavoidable Conditions of the Real Speech Situation. Social Epistemology, 27(3–4), 199–246. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2013.818733

Susen, S. (2014). 15 Theses on Power. Philosophy and Society, 25(3), 7–28. https://doi.org/10.2298/FID1403007S

Susen, S. (2015). The ‘Postmodern Turn’ in the Social Sciences. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137318237

Susen, S. (2016a). Pierre Bourdieu et la distinction sociale. Un essai philosophique. Oxford: Peter Lang.

Susen, S. (2016b). The Sociological Challenge of Reflexivity in Bourdieusian Thought. In D. Robbins (Eds.), The Anthem Companion to Pierre Bourdieu (pp. 49–93). London: Anthem Press.

Susen, S. (2016c). Towards a Critical Sociology of Dominant Ideologies: An Unexpected Reunion between Pierre Bourdieu and Luc Boltanski. Cultural Sociology, 10(2), 195–246. https://doi.org/10.1177/1749975515593098

Susen, S. (2016d). Reconstructing the Self: A Goffmanian Perspective. In H.F. Dahms & E.R. Lybeck (Eds.), Reconstructing Social Theory, History and Practice, Vol 35: Current Perspectives in Social Theory (pp. 111–143). Bingley: Emerald.

Susen, S. (2018). The Seductive Force of ‘Noumenal Power’: A New Path (or Impasse) for Critical Theory? Journal of Political Power, 11(1), 4–45. https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379X.2017.1362734

Susen, S. (2021a). Contemporary Social Theory. In K. Murji, S. Neal, & J. Solomos (Eds.), An Introduction to Sociology (pp. 121–141). London: Sage.

Susen, S. (2021b). Mysteries, Conspiracies, and Inquiries: Reflections on the Power of Superstition, Suspicion, and Scrutiny. Società Mutamento Politica: Rivista Italiana di Sociologia, 12(23), 25–62. https://oajournals.fupress.net/index.php/smp/article/view/12996/12267

Susen, S. (2022a). The Case for a Critical Hermeneutics: From the Understanding of Power to the Power of Understanding. In L. Dunaj & K.C.M. Mertel (Eds.), Hans-Herbert Kögler’s Critical Hermeneutics (pp. 7–69). London: Bloomsbury.

Susen, S. (2022b). Critical Remarks on Existence Theory: Between Existentialism and Phenomenology. Journal of Classical Sociology, 22(1), 49–84. https://doi.org/10.1177/1468795X211051514

Susen, S. (2023a). Lessons from Reckwitz and Rosa: Towards a Constructive Dialogue between Critical Analytics and Critical Theory. Social Epistemology, 37(5), 545–591. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2201578

Susen, S. (2023b). Towards an Ontology of Contemporary Reality? Theory, Culture & Society, 40(7–8), 33–55. https://doi.org/10.1177/02632764221143943

Susen, S. (2023c). A New Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere? With, against, and beyond Habermas. Society, 60(6), 842–867. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12115-023-00908-y

Taylor, C. (1977). Interpretation and the Sciences of Man. In F.R. Dallmayr & T.A. McCarthy (Eds.), Understanding and Social Inquiry (pp. 101–131). South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

Thévenot, L. (2007). The Plurality of Cognitive Formats and Engagements: Moving between the Familiar and the Public. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 409–423. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368431007080703

Triandis, H.C. (1996). The Psychological Measurement of Cultural Syndromes. American Psychologist, 51(4), 407–415. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.51.4.407

Turner, S. (2007). Social Theory as a Cognitive Neuroscience. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 357–374. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368431007080700

Tylor, E.B. (1881). Anthropology: An Introduction to the Study of Man and Civilization. London: Macmillan.

Tylor, E.B. (1920). Primitive Culture: Researches into the Development of Mythology, Philosophy, Religion, Language, Art and Custom. London: John Murray. (Original work published 1871)

van Inwagen, P., & Zimmerman, D.W. (Eds.). (2008). Metaphysics: The Big Questions (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. (Original work published 1998)

Wacquant, L. (1992). Epistemic Reflexivity. In P. Bourdieu & L. Wacquant, An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology (pp. 36–46). Cambridge: Polity.

Ward, A. (2006). Kant: The Three Critiques. Cambridge: Polity.

Ward, K. (2008). The Big Questions in Science and Religion. West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Foundation Press.

Weber, M. (1980). Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriß der verstehenden Soziologie (5th ed.). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. (Original work published 1922)

Weintraub, J.A., & Kumar, K. (Eds.). (1997). Public and Private in Thought and Practice: Perspectives on a Grand Dichotomy. Chicago IL: University of Chicago Press.

Whiting, D. (Eds.). (2010). The Later Wittgenstein on Language. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

Williams, R. (1994). The Analysis of Culture. In J. Storey (Eds.), Cultural Theory and Popular Culture: A Reader (pp. 48–56). New York, NY: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

Wilson, E.O. (2004). On Human Nature (25th Anniversary ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Original work published 1978)

Wittgenstein, L. (2009). Philosophical Investigations (G.E.M. Anscombe, P.M.S. Hacker, & J. Schulte, Trans.) (4th ed.). Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. (Original work published 1953)


  1. See Geertz (1973).↩︎

  2. See ibid., esp. Part I / Chapter 1: ‘Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture’ (pp. 3–30).↩︎

  3. See ibid., esp. Part I / Chapter 1: ‘Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture’ (pp. 3–30).↩︎

  4. See Ryle (2009), Chapter 37: ‘The Thinking of Thoughts: What is “Le Penseur” Doing?’ (1968).↩︎

  5. Geertz (1973, p. 6).↩︎

  6. See ibid., pp. 6–10.↩︎

  7. Ibid., p. 7.↩︎

  8. Ibid., p. 7 (italics in original).↩︎

  9. Ibid., p. 9.↩︎

  10. Ibid., p. 9.↩︎

  11. Ibid., p. 9 (italics added).↩︎

  12. Ibid., p. 9 (italics added).↩︎

  13. Ibid., p. 9.↩︎

  14. Ibid., p. 9.↩︎

  15. Ibid., pp. 9–10 & 16.↩︎

  16. Ibid., p. 10.↩︎

  17. Geertz stresses the (useful) ambiguity of Durkheim’s concept of conscience collective, which—arguably—may refer to both collective conscience and collective consciousness. On this point, see ibid., p. 316.↩︎

  18. Ibid., p. 10.↩︎

  19. Ibid., p. 10.↩︎

  20. Ibid., p. 10 (spelling modified).↩︎

  21. Ibid., p. 10.↩︎

  22. Ibid., p. 10.↩︎

  23. Ibid., p. 20.↩︎

  24. Ibid., p. 21.↩︎

  25. Ibid., p. 21 (italics added). On this point, see, for example: Chernilo (2017); Habermas (2003); Honneth & Joas (1988); Pinker (2002); Wilson (2004).↩︎

  26. Geertz (1973, p. 13).↩︎

  27. See Cavell (2002).↩︎

  28. Ibid., pp. 67–68 (italics in original). See Geertz (1973, p. 13).↩︎

  29. Cavell (2002, p. 68) (italics in original). See Geertz (1973, p. 13).↩︎

  30. Ibid., p. 6.↩︎

  31. See Tylor (1920, p. 1). See also Tylor (1881).↩︎

  32. See Kluckhohn (1949).↩︎

  33. See Geertz (1973, pp. 4–5).↩︎

  34. See ibid., p. 4: ‘the total way of life of a people’.↩︎

  35. See ibid., p. 4: ‘the social legacy the individual acquires from his group’.↩︎

  36. See ibid., p. 4: ‘a way of thinking, feeling, and believing’.↩︎

  37. See ibid., p. 4: ‘an abstraction from behaviour’ (spelling modified).↩︎

  38. See ibid., p. 4: ‘a theory on the part of the anthropologist about the way in which a group of people in fact behave’.↩︎

  39. See ibid., pp. 4–5: ‘a “store house of pooled learning”’.↩︎

  40. See ibid., p. 5: ‘a set of standardized orientations to recurrent problems’.↩︎

  41. See ibid., p. 5: ‘learned behaviour’.↩︎

  42. See ibid., p. 5: ‘a mechanism for the normative regulation of behaviour’.↩︎

  43. See ibid., p. 5: ‘a set of techniques for adjusting both to the external environment and to other men’.↩︎

  44. See ibid., p. 5: ‘a precipitate of history’.↩︎

  45. See ibid., p. 5: ‘as a map, as a sieve, and as a matrix’.↩︎

  46. Ibid., p. 5.↩︎

  47. Ibid., p. 5 (italics added).↩︎

  48. Ibid., p. 5.↩︎

  49. Ibid., p. 5 (italics added).↩︎

  50. Ibid., p. 10.↩︎

  51. Ibid., p. 11.↩︎

  52. Ibid., p. 11.↩︎

  53. Ibid., p. 11. Cf. Goodenough (2006) and Goodenough (1981). Cf. also Keesing (1974, pp. 85–86).↩︎

  54. See Geertz (1973, p. 11).↩︎

  55. Ibid., p. 11.↩︎

  56. Ibid., p. 20.↩︎

  57. Ibid., p. 20.↩︎

  58. See ibid., pp. 16, 17, 18, 20, 25, 29, 30, 222n45, 364, 405, & 407.↩︎

  59. Ibid., p. 20 (italics added).↩︎

  60. Ibid., p. 20 (italics added). Cf. Susen (2007, pp. 158–167).↩︎

  61. Ibid., p. 12.↩︎

  62. Wittgenstein (2009, §43). On this point, see also Susen (2023b, esp. section VII).↩︎

  63. See Husserl (2001), Husserl (2012), and Husserl (1970).↩︎

  64. See Wittgenstein (2009).↩︎

  65. Geertz (1973, p. 12). Cf. Kripke (1982).↩︎

  66. Geertz (1973, p. 12) (italics added).↩︎

  67. Cf. Geertz (1988).↩︎

  68. See Wittgenstein (2009).↩︎

  69. Ibid., p. 223. See Geertz (1973, p. 13). Cf. Hunter (1968, esp. p. 242).↩︎

  70. Wittgenstein (2009, p. 223). See Geertz (1973, p. 13). Cf. Hunter (1968, esp. p. 242).↩︎

  71. On the noumenal/phenomenal distinction, see Kant (1995). See also Oberst (2015) and Ward (2006), Part I. In addition, see Susen (2021b, esp. p. 44) and Susen (2023b, Part IX, sections 3 & 4).↩︎

  72. Geertz (1973, p. 22) (italics added).↩︎

  73. Ibid., p. 22 (italics added).↩︎

  74. Cf. Rosa (2020).↩︎

  75. Geertz (1973, p. 3) (italics added).↩︎

  76. See Berger & Luckmann (1967).↩︎

  77. See Susen (2015, pp. 5–6, 239, & 245). See also Susen (2021a, esp. pp. 121–129).↩︎

  78. See Langer (1942).↩︎

  79. Geertz (1973, p. 4).↩︎

  80. On the ‘demarcation problem’, see, for instance: Lakatos et al. (1999); Laudan (1983); Lloyd (1983); Resnik (2000); Susen (2015, esp. pp. 49 & 56).↩︎

  81. Cf. Einstein (1934), p. 165: ‘It can scarcely be denied that the supreme goal of all theory is to make the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience’.↩︎

  82. Geertz (1973, p. 5).↩︎

  83. Ibid., p. 5.↩︎

  84. Ibid., p. 5 (italics added).↩︎

  85. Ibid., p. 5 (italics added).↩︎

  86. Ibid., p. 5 (italics added).↩︎

  87. Geertz (1973, p. 14).↩︎

  88. Ibid., p. 14 (italics added).↩︎

  89. See Susen (2014, p. 8). See also Susen (2015, pp. 117–118) and Susen (2018).↩︎

  90. Geertz (1973, p. 14).↩︎

  91. On the paradigm of understanding [Verstehen], see, for instance: Apel (1984); Baert (2003, esp. pp. 100–102); Baert (2005); Bourdieu (1993); Celikates (2018); Dallmayr & McCarthy (1977); Dilthey (1883); Habermas (1987); Kögler & Stueber (2000); Outhwaite (1986); Outhwaite (2000, esp. pp. 223–227); Taylor (1977); Weber (1980).↩︎

  92. On this point, see Geertz (1973, p. 14) (‘the verstehen approach’ [sic]) and Geertz (1973, p. 88) (‘Weber’s Verstehenden methodology’ [sic]).↩︎

  93. See ibid., p. 14 (italics in original): ‘Nothing is more necessary to comprehending what anthropological interpretation is, and the degree to which it is interpretation, than an exact understanding of what it means—and what it does not mean—to say that our formulations of other peoples’ symbol systems must be actor-oriented’.↩︎

  94. Ibid., p. 15.↩︎

  95. Ibid., p. 16.↩︎

  96. Ibid., p. 16 (italics added).↩︎

  97. Ibid., p. 16.↩︎

  98. Ibid., p. 16.↩︎

  99. Ibid., p. 16.↩︎

  100. Ibid., p. 17.↩︎

  101. Ibid., p. 17.↩︎

  102. Ibid., p. 17 (spelling modified).↩︎

  103. Ibid., p. 17.↩︎

  104. See Wittgenstein (2009, §43). On this point, see also Susen (2023b, esp. section VII).↩︎

  105. Geertz (1973, p. 17).↩︎

  106. Ibid., p. 17.↩︎

  107. See ibid., p. 17.↩︎

  108. Ibid., p. 18.↩︎

  109. Ibid., p. 18.↩︎

  110. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  111. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  112. Cf. Geertz (1984).↩︎

  113. Geertz (1973, p. 23).↩︎

  114. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  115. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  116. See ibid., pp. 21–23.↩︎

  117. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  118. Ibid., p. 23 (italics in original).↩︎

  119. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  120. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  121. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  122. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  123. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  124. Ibid., p. 24.↩︎

  125. Ibid., p. 24.↩︎

  126. Ibid., p. 24 (italics added).↩︎

  127. Ibid., p. 24.↩︎

  128. Ibid., p. 24.↩︎

  129. Ibid., p. 24 (italics added).↩︎

  130. Ibid., p. 24.↩︎

  131. Ibid., p. 24.↩︎

  132. Ibid., p. 24.↩︎

  133. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  134. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  135. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  136. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  137. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  138. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  139. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  140. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  141. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  142. Ibid., p. 25.↩︎

  143. Ibid., p. 26.↩︎

  144. Ibid., p. 26 (italics added).↩︎

  145. See ibid., p. 26.↩︎

  146. Ibid., p. 26.↩︎

  147. Ibid., p. 26 (italics added).↩︎

  148. See ibid., p. 27: ‘Theoretical ideas are not created wholly anew in each study; […] they are adopted from other, related studies, and, refined in the process, applied to new interpretive problems. If they cease being useful with respect to such problems, they tend to stop being used and are more or less abandoned. If they continue being useful, throwing up new understandings, they are further elaborated and go on being used’. On this point, see also ibid., p. 27n5.↩︎

  149. Ibid., p. 27 (italics added).↩︎

  150. Ibid., p. 27 (italics added).↩︎

  151. Ibid., p. 27.↩︎

  152. Ibid., p. 27.↩︎

  153. Ibid., p. 27 (spelling modified).↩︎

  154. Cf. Geertz (2000).↩︎

  155. Geertz (1973, p. 27) (italics added).↩︎

  156. See ibid., pp. 27–28.↩︎

  157. Ibid., p. 23.↩︎

  158. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  159. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  160. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  161. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  162. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  163. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  164. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  165. Ibid., p. 28.↩︎

  166. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  167. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  168. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  169. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  170. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  171. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  172. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  173. Ibid., p. 29. Cf. Gallie (1955). Cf. also Collier et al. (2006).↩︎

  174. Geertz (1973, p. 29).↩︎

  175. Ibid., p. 29.↩︎

  176. Ibid., p. 30.↩︎

  177. Ibid., p. 30.↩︎

  178. Ibid., p. 30.↩︎

  179. On ‘the big questions’, see, for instance: Alcoff (1998); Baggini (2012); Blackburn (2009); Keller (2010); Korsmeyer (1998); Nye (1998); Sherratt & Wilkinson (2009); Solomon & Higgins (2014); Sterba (2009); Stump & Murray (1999); van Inwagen & Zimmerman (2008); Ward (2008).↩︎

  180. See Geertz (1973, p. 9).↩︎

  181. Cf. Joas (1991).↩︎

  182. Geertz (1973, p. 10).↩︎

  183. Ibid., p. 22 (italics added).↩︎

  184. Ibid., p. 22 (italics added).↩︎

  185. Ibid., p. 18.↩︎

  186. Ibid., p. 18 (italics in original).↩︎

  187. On this point, see Bourdieu (1980, p. 67) and Bourdieu (1998, p. 9). See also Susen (2013b, pp. 212 & 226).↩︎

  188. See Susen (2015, pp. 93–94).↩︎

  189. See ibid., pp. 94–96.↩︎

  190. See ibid., pp. 96–101.↩︎

  191. See ibid., pp. 101–108.↩︎

  192. See ibid., pp. 108–110.↩︎

  193. Cf. Sewell (1999).↩︎

  194. On this point, see, for instance: Susen (2011a, esp. pp. 174–175); Susen (2013a, pp. 92–93); Susen (2015, pp. 93–110); Susen (2016a, esp. pp. 5, 15, 24, 28–29, 32–33, 40, 54–57, & 70–73); Triandis (1996, esp. pp. 408–409); Williams (1994, esp. p. 48).↩︎

  195. Geertz (1973, p. 11). Cf. Goodenough (2006) and Goodenough (1981). Cf. also Keesing (1974, pp. 85–86).↩︎

  196. On ‘cognitive anthropology’, see, for instance: Beller et al. (2012); Bender & Beller (2015); Bloch (2012); Brown (2006); Carey (2015); D'Andrade (1995); Ingold (2015); Kaufmann & Clément (2015); Regnier & Astuti (2015); Pharo (2007); Strauss (2006).↩︎

  197. On ‘cognitive sociology’ (and ‘cognitive social theory’), see, for instance: Boltanski & Thévenot (2000); Bouvier (2007); Brekhus & Ignatow (2019); Cerulo (2010); Cicourel (1974); DiMaggio (1997); Eder (2007); Strydom (2007); Strydom (2015); Thévenot (2007); Turner (2007).↩︎

  198. On ‘neuroscientific approaches’, see, for instance: Cerulo (2010); Hurley & Chater (2005); Roitblat et al. (1993); Turner (2007).↩︎

  199. On the concept of ‘normative orders’, see Forst & Günther (2011a) and Forst & Günther (2011b). See also, for instance: Forst (2002); Forst (2012); Forst (2013a); Forst (2013b); Forst (2013c); Forst (2014); Forst (2015a); Forst (2015b); Forst (2017); Forst et al. (2009); Susen (2018, pp. 11–14, 26–28, & 31).↩︎

  200. Geertz (1973, p. 12) (italics added).↩︎

  201. See Wittgenstein (2009, §43). On this point, see also Susen (2023b, esp. section VII).↩︎

  202. See Wittgenstein (2009, esp. §243–315). On this point, see also, for example: Habermas (2001); Floyd (2020); Hunter (1968); Kripke (1982); Whiting (2010).↩︎

  203. See Adorno (1973, pp. 183–189). On this point, see also, for example: Morgan (2017); Susen (2007, p. 218); Susen (2011a, pp. 186 & 190); Susen (2022a, p. 10).↩︎

  204. On this point, see, for instance: Bailey (2000); Butt & Langdridge (2003); Condren (2009); Crouch (2016); Cutler (1997); Geuss (2001); Habermas (1962); Habermas (1989); Marston (1995); Powell & Clemens (1998); Salmerón Castro (2002); Steinberger (1999); Susen (2011b); Susen (2023c); Weintraub & Kumar (1997).↩︎

  205. See Triandis (1996, esp. pp. 408–409). (According to Triandis’s typology, the following main ‘cultural syndromes’ can be identified: tightness, cultural complexity, active–passive, honour, collectivism, individualism, and vertical and horizontal relationships). On this point, see also, for example: Susen (2007, pp. 63–64, 214, & 290); Susen (2010, pp. 67–68 & 77–78); Susen (2012, p. 309); Susen (2015, p. 140); Susen (2016a, p. 72); Susen (2016d, pp. 132–133); Susen (2022b, p. 65).↩︎

  206. Wittgenstein (2009, p. 223). See Geertz (1973, p. 13). Cf. Hunter (1968, esp. p. 242).↩︎

  207. On this point, see, for instance: Chambers (2022); Dunaj & Mertel (2022); Kögler (1996); Kurasawa (2003); Susen (2022a).↩︎

  208. On the concept of ‘epistemological break’, see, for instance: Bourdieu (1999, pp. 334–335); Bourdieu & Eagleton (1992, esp. p. 117); Bourdieu et al. (2011); Bourdieu & Wacquant (1992a, p. 150); Bourdieu & Wacquant (1992b, p. 213); Robbins (1998); Susen (2007, pp. 135–137 & 261–262); Susen (2016b, pp. 62–66); Susen (2016c, p. 217).↩︎

  209. See Susen (2021a, pp. 126–127).↩︎

  210. Geertz (1973, p. 15).↩︎

  211. On this point, see, for example, Susen (2007, p. 167). See also Susen (2023a, pp. 566 & 571).↩︎

  212. On this point, see, for instance: Archer (2007); Barnard (1990); Bohman (1997); Bourdieu (2004); Burkitt (1997); Celikates (2018[2009]); Kögler (1996); Susen (2016b); Wacquant (1992).↩︎

  213. Geertz (1973, p. 17).↩︎

  214. On this point, see, for instance, Cossu (2021) and Cossu (2022).↩︎

  215. On this point, see, for instance, Susen (2007, pp. 179, 191, 207, & 265). See also Susen (2013b, pp. 211 & 228).↩︎

  216. See Bourdieu (1997, pp. 116–117).↩︎

  217. See Susen (2007, p. 265).↩︎

  218. Translation from German into English: ‘interpretation of the world’.↩︎

  219. Translation from German into English: ‘need for meaning’.↩︎

  220. Cf. Susen (2007, esp. Chapter 9).↩︎